Zulip Chat Archive
Stream: new members
Topic: formalizing Hilbert's axioms for plane geometry
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:35):
Hi there, I'm a mathematician getting started with Lean. After having done the natural number game and a few of the challenges, I wanted to start formalizing something easy, and I tried with Hilber'ts axioms.
So far, I have this little:
import tactic -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle local attribute [instance, priority 0] classical.prop_decidable noncomputable theory open_locale classical constants Points Lines : Type* constant lies_on : Points → Lines → Prop local infixl `∈` := lies_on constant I1 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃! ℓ, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) --constant I11 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃ ℓ, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) --constant I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s : Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s constant I2 : ∀ ℓ : Lines, ∃ A B : Points, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ constant I3 : ∃ A B C : Points, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) ))) lemma I11 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃ ℓ, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) := begin intros A B, intro h, cases I1 A B h with ℓ h1, existsi ℓ, cases h1 with H, exact H, end lemma I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s : Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s := begin intros A B, intros r s, intro h, intro hAr, intro hBr, intro hAs, intro hBs, cases I1 A B h with ℓ h1, have r_is_ell : r = ℓ, ... end
The axiom I1 is an if and only if statement, and I wanted to separate the two statements as I11 and I12. I succeeded with I11 (existence) but for I12 (uniqueness) I am having trouble. I end up with the following tactic state:
A B : Points, r s : Lines, h : A ≠ B, hAr : A∈r, hBr : B∈r, hAs : A∈s, hBs : B∈s, ℓ : Lines, h1 : (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) ℓ ∧ ∀ (y : Lines), (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) y → y = ℓ ⊢ r = s
and then I want to conclude by showing that r = ell = s, so I do have r_eq_ell : r = \ell
. This gives me the first goal of showing r = ell, and there I get stuck:
2 goals A B : Points, r s : Lines, h : A ≠ B, hAr : A∈r, hBr : B∈r, hAs : A∈s, hBs : B∈s, ℓ : Lines, h1 : (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) ℓ ∧ ∀ (y : Lines), (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) y → y = ℓ ⊢ r = ℓ A B : Points, r s : Lines, h : A ≠ B, hAr : A∈r, hBr : B∈r, hAs : A∈s, hBs : B∈s, ℓ : Lines, h1 : (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) ℓ ∧ ∀ (y : Lines), (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) y → y = ℓ, r_eq_ell : r = ℓ ⊢ r = s
Thank you for any help!
PS: I know that I should be using classes or structures, but I am trying to keep it as simple as possible (and using as few non-math concepts as possible). Once I get something compiling I will try to understand how to make it up to standards.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:39):
@Marc Masdeu I think there are functions unique_of_exists_unique
that take an ∃! foobar
statement, and spit out the corresponding uniqueness statement.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:39):
But maybe you would rather prove it by yourself, as an exercise.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:41):
Good to know (I had seen it elsewhere) but I would like to prove the exact statement of I12 (yes, as an exercice), and more so now that I got stuck :-).
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:41):
have r_is_ell : r = ℓ, { apply h1.right, split, assumption' },
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:42):
Alternative:
rcases I1 A B h with ⟨ℓ, h1_left, h1_right⟩, have r_is_ell : r = ℓ, { apply h1_right, split, assumption' },
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:42):
I changed cases
to rcases
. That allows you to do "recursive" cases. (And I didn't attempt to give meaningful names to the hypotheses)
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:43):
aha! Is there a way to resolve the have with tactics? I am not so comfortable yet with switching from one way to the other..
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:44):
What do you mean?
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:45):
I proved the have
using tactics. I used { ... }
to "zoom in" on one goal
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:45):
But you don't need to write those curly braces, if you don't want to
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:45):
Or do you want to avoid the have
altogether?
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:45):
Oh I see. I am trying myself now. I thought that the {} was used to construct directly a term. I am in the right thread...
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:47):
rcases I1 A B h with ⟨ℓ, h1_left, h1_right⟩, transitivity, { apply h1_right, split, assumption' }, { symmetry, apply h1_right, split, assumption' }
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:47):
Proof without have
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:47):
Shorter version:
rcases I1 A B h with ⟨ℓ, h1_left, h1_right⟩, transitivity, swap, symmetry, all_goals { apply h1_right, split, assumption' },
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:47):
OK, I got it. I thought that h1 was a function so that I could apply it by doing something like h1 r
but this never worked. I hadn't thought of doing the .right
and I still don't see the reasoning behind it.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:48):
Sure, it also took me some time to parse it. But it is of the form ... ∧ ...
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:48):
And the right hand side is a function
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:49):
Oh! How can I check this kind of things inside a proof? If h1 was defined outside, I would start trying #check h1
, #check h1 r
and so on, but I couldn't do anything like that inside the proof...
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:50):
Are you using VScode?
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:50):
Because it lists your entire context in the tactic state
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:51):
In the same place where you would see the output of #check foobar
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:51):
No, I'm using cocalc (I want some summer camp students to be able to play around with this, and wanted to set something up easy to use for them)
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:51):
But where do you see the output of #check h1
in CoCalc?
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:51):
Probably in some message window somewhere
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:52):
You are also seeing the goal that you want to prove somewhere. Right above it should be a list of all your hypotheses.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:52):
Yes, there is a message window. But if I want to know the type of something, for example, I can't ask for it there.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:52):
I'm copy-pasting this from your first message:
2 goals A B : Points, r s : Lines, h : A ≠ B, hAr : A∈r, hBr : B∈r, hAs : A∈s, hBs : B∈s, ℓ : Lines, h1 : (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) ℓ ∧ ∀ (y : Lines), (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) y → y = ℓ ⊢ r = ℓ
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:53):
Yes, I see the hypotheses and everything, and they get updated as I advance. A lot like the web interface of the natural number game. What I don't have is autocompletion.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:53):
That's where you can see h1 : (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) ℓ ∧ ∀ (y : Lines), (λ (ℓ : Lines), A∈ℓ ∧ B∈ℓ) y → y = ℓ
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:53):
That's the type of h1
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:53):
Hmm... what exactly do you mean? I thought CoCalc had some form of autocomplete
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:56):
I don't think it has any autocompletion (unless I have it disabled somehow!). What I meant --and maybe it's still me being stupid-- is that if I want to run some command (like h1 r
) inside the proof to see what it would give me, I will probably get a useless error.
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 08:56):
If you are in a tactic block and you want to know the type of something you can have what_am_i := thing_I_dont_know,
then in the info at cursor block you should see what_am_i : ℕ
or whatever it is
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:57):
Oh @Alex J. Best this is clever! Thanks.
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 08:57):
Screen-Shot-2020-01-15-at-14.27.06.png
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:57):
@Marc Masdeu Aha, I see. This might be one way to "hack" it:
rcases I1 A B h with ⟨ℓ, h1⟩, have test := h1 r,
This will give you an error
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 08:57):
Aah, ok, Alex beat me (-;
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:58):
You guys are incredibly helpful! Thanks!!
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 08:58):
This is normally how I build terms, start with a function /lemma I want to apply with no arguments as have, then add arguments one by one till it gets to what I want.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 08:59):
Aha. Yes, I want to learn how to translate the way we do math usually, into Lean.
I'll go back and try to prove a few more stupid lemmas. Probably will come back very soon...
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 09:00):
Good luck! (-;
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 09:00):
Some form of tab completion works for me in Cocalc by the way Screen-Shot-2020-01-15-at-14.30.23.png
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 09:01):
I typed apply and.
then hit tab, the first 20 results were random general things, but then it showed me various and
related lemmas and their types.
Actually it worked better when I did apply a
then tab then continued typing. I think the .
was doing something a little funny with the tab completion.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 09:07):
I'll try. I seem to remember that in VScode the completion appeared without the tab, this confused me.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 12:15):
OK, so I'm a bit further down. So far, I have:
import tactic -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle local attribute [instance, priority 0] classical.prop_decidable noncomputable theory open_locale classical universe u constant Points : Type u constant Lines : set(set Points) constant lies_on : Points → Lines → Prop local infixl `∈` := lies_on notation x `∋` y := lies_on y x constant I1 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃! ℓ, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) constant I2 : ∀ ℓ : Lines, ∃ A B : Points, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ constant I3 : ∃ A B C : Points, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) ))) notation p `xor` q := (p ∧ ¬ q) ∨ (q ∧ ¬ p) lemma I11 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃ ℓ, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) := begin intros A B, intro h, cases I1 A B h with ℓ h1, existsi ℓ, cases h1 with H, exact H, end lemma I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s : Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s := begin intros A B, intros r s, intro h, intro hAr, intro hBr, intro hAs, intro hBs, cases I1 A B h with ℓ h1, transitivity ℓ, have r_eq_ell : r = ℓ, apply h1.right, split, exact hAr, exact hBr, exact r_eq_ell, have s_eq_ell : s = ℓ, apply h1.right, split, exact hAs, exact hBs, symmetry, exact s_eq_ell, end lemma there_are_two_points : ∃ A B : Points, (A ≠ B) := begin cases I3 with A BCh, cases BCh with B Ch, cases Ch with C h, cases h with hh, existsi A, existsi B, exact hh, end lemma distinct_lines_have_at_most_one_common_point {r s : Lines} {A B : Points} (hrs: r ≠ s) (hAr: A ∈ r) (hAs: A ∈ s) (hBr: B ∈ r) (hBs: B ∈ s) : A = B := begin suffices not_A_eq_B : ¬ (A ≠ B), cc, intro h, suffices Q : r = s, contradiction, exact I12 A B r s h hAr hBr hAs hBs, end definition intersect (r s : Lines) := ∃ A : Points, A ∈ r ∧ A∈ s definition parallel (r s : Lines) := (r = s) ∨ (¬ intersect r s) local infixl `||` := parallel constant parallel_postulate {A : Points} {ℓ r s : Lines} : A ∈ r ∧ A ∈ s ∧ r || ℓ ∧ s || ℓ → r = s constant between : Points → Points → Points → Prop notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C definition colinear (A B C : Points) := ∃ ℓ : Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ -- definition noncolinear (A B C : Points) := ¬ colinear A B C constant B11 {A B C : Points} : (A * B * C) → (C * B * A) constant B12 {A B C : Points} : (A * B * C) → (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ colinear A B C) constant B2 {A B : Points} : ∃ C, A * B * C constant B3 {A B C : Points} {ℓ : Lines} : (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ) → ((A * B * C) ∧ ¬( B * A * C ) ∧ ¬ (A * C * B)) ∨ (¬ (A * B * C) ∧ ( B * A * C ) ∧ ¬ (A * C * B)) ∨ (¬ (A * B * C) ∧ ¬( B * A * C ) ∧ (A * C * B)) -- constant B4 {A B C D: Points} {ℓ : Lines}: (noncolinear A B C) ∧ (¬ A ∈ ℓ) ∧ (¬ B ∈ ℓ) ∧ (¬ C ∈ ℓ) ∧ (D ∈ ℓ) ∧ (A * D * B) → (∃ E : Points, (A * E * C) xor (B * E * C)) def line_segment (A B : Points) : set Points := {A} ∪ {B} ∪ {C : Points | A * C * B} local infix `#` := line_segment def triangle (A B C : Points) (h: colinear A B C) : set Points := A#B ∪ A#C ∪ B#C lemma segments_are_symmetric: ∀ A B : Points, A # B = B # A := begin intros A B, rw set.subset.antisymm_iff, split, intro x, intro h, have hh : x = A ∨ x = B ∨ A * x * B, { cases h with h1 h2, cases h1 with ha hb, left, cases ha, exact ha, exfalso, exact ha, cases hb, right, left, exact hb, exfalso, exact hb, right, right, exact h2, }, cases hh with H1 H2, left, right, rw set.singleton_def, left, exact H1, cases H2 with H G, left, left, rw set.singleton_def, left, exact H, right, ... end
I am trying to prove that the segments AB and BA are the same, and I'm having lots of trouble. The "math" way to prove it is:
recall that AB is defined to be the union of {A}, {B} and the points in between A and B. We have axiom I12 which says that x is betwen A and B implies x is between B and A. So obviously the segments AB and BA are equal. What I do in Lean is quite longer, but first I turn to a double inclusion (I would like to know how to prove the second one "by symmetry"), and I'm trying to finish one of the inclusions. I'm at the point where it's "enough" to apply axiom I12: my goal looks like:
A B x : Points, h : x ∈ A#B, G : A * x*B ⊢ x ∈ {C : Points | B * C*A}
and I want to tell Lean to "expand" hypothesis G and use I12. Any hints?
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:18):
Ooof, some of your lines are quite long (-;
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:21):
In your definition of triangle
, I think you want ¬ colinear A B C
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:24):
Also, the Lean keyword for ...
is sorry
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:26):
@Marc Masdeu Here is one way to use symmetry to reduce to 1 inclusion:
begin suffices : ∀ A B : Points, A # B ⊆ B # A, { intros A B, apply set.subset.antisymm; solve_by_elim }, intros A B, intro x, intro h, sorry
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:27):
Ideally, the wlog
tactic would do this for you. But I usually end up in a big fight if I try to use it.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:30):
@Marc Masdeu Here's another hint: First prove two lemmas A ∈ A#B
and B ∈ A#B
. They will be useful in lots of places.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:33):
Also, you overwrote the standard meaning of ∈
, so my suggestions no longer typecheck
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:39):
lemma segments_are_symmetric: ∀ A B : Points, A # B = B # A := begin suffices : ∀ A B : Points, A # B ⊆ B # A, { intros A B, apply set.subset.antisymm; solve_by_elim }, intros A B, intros x h, rcases h with ⟨⟨rfl | ⟨⟨⟩⟩⟩ | rfl | ⟨⟨⟩⟩⟩ | h, { unfold line_segment, finish }, { unfold line_segment, finish }, { unfold line_segment, have := B11 h, finish }, end
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:39):
@Marc Masdeu I found that crazy rcases
line, by writing rcases? h
and copying from the message window.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:40):
All those weird brackets and rfl
s tell Lean that most of the things you need to do are really very trivial.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:40):
What remains are the (mildly :wink:) interesting cases.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 12:42):
finish
is a tactic that says: "Given the current hypothesis, this is elementary logic. I can do that."
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 12:53):
Just for fun I did this too without looking at Johan's, I think they're fundamentally the same? I didn't know the crazy rcases
thing though.
lemma segments_are_symmetric: ∀ A B : Points, A # B = B # A := begin suffices : ∀ A B : Points, A # B ⊆ B # A, { intros, exact le_antisymm (this A B) (this B A),-- i just typed library_search to get this, }, rintros A B x hx, unfold line_segment at *, simp at *, rw or.assoc at hx, apply or.elim3 hx, all_goals {intros,try{cc},}, apply or.intro_right, exact B11 a, end
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:04):
Thanks guys, I'm studying your solutions now...
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:08):
About @Johan Commelin complaint about long lines: I definitely agree with it, but how would you go about writing the simple statement "Given three distinct points on a line, exactly one of them is between the other two" in a concise way?
Alex J. Best (Jan 15 2020 at 13:09):
I guess Johan just means put some line breaks in at natural looking points (lean won't care)
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:20):
I guess Johan just means put some line breaks in at natural looking points (lean won't care)
Oh :sweat_smile:
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:32):
Also, you overwrote the standard meaning of
∈
, so my suggestions no longer typecheck
@Johan Commelin to solve this, I have decided to go back to set theory. That means that Points should be a set, and that Lines should be a set of sets of points. If I initialize
Points : set Type u Lines : set set Points
then my axioms start to misbehave, because I assume that it doesn't make sense to write A : Points and instead I should write someting like A \in Points. Am I right?
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:37):
I would be tempted to let points be in a type, and lines be subsets of points, if you want to go down the subset route.
Kenny Lau (Jan 15 2020 at 13:37):
one would first have to prove lines.ext
then
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:40):
I can prove that
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:41):
it follows from propext
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:41):
I would be tempted to let points be in a type, and lines be subsets of points, if you want to go down the subset route.
I have two reasons to do that: I am trying to copy Hartshorne's UTM book and he defines points to be a set. The second reason is so that in this way I don't need to define what A \in ell means.
Your intermediate approach seems to solve my second concern, I will try that.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:42):
one would first have to prove
lines.ext
then
What is that?
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:43):
he defines points to be a set
That's because he's thinking about framing things in terms of set theory. There are two kinds of sets. There are subsets of a given set, like the even numbers, and there are generic sets about which we know nothing -- and in type theory those are types.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:43):
lines.ext
is the statement that two lines are equal if and only for all points P, P is in line 1 iff it's in line 2. One can prove this in Lean no problem.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:45):
In contrast to the "generic" set of points, a line is a subset. Subsets are different to sets.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:46):
And two subsets are not automatically equal iff they contain the same elements? I am getting lost.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:46):
I don't know anything about the various ways of doing this stuff. I know that Ali Sever followed Tarski, and IIRC a line was an abstract type. What does Hartshorne do?
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:46):
And two subsets are not automatically equal iff they contain the same elements? I am getting lost.
It is a trivial theorem, but it is not true by definition.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:47):
In fact it is equivalent to propositional extensionality, which is talked about at great length here. As a mathematician you should just ignore all this. Kenny is a constructivist, he is just trolling really.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:48):
Remember that in set theory there is an axiom which says that two sets with the same elements are equal.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:49):
Equal sets have the same elements -- this is obvious. Sets with the same elements are equal -- this is a theorem, whose one-line proof is "it's an axiom"
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:49):
so you will have to supply a one-line proof ;-)
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:49):
From Hartshorne: "We simply postulate a set, whose elements are called points, together with certain subsets, which we call lines. We do not say what the points are, nor which subsets form lines, but we do require that these undefined notions obey certain axioms..."
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:50):
OK so you should make a type of points, and let lines be subsets. Then everything will work just the way Hartshorne wants.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:52):
Equal sets have the same elements -- this is obvious. Sets with the same elements are equal -- this is a theorem, whose one-line proof is "it's an axiom"
Oh. And Lean standard doesn't come with these theorems proven for you? I would imagine that if Lean knows what a set is, then it knows all the basic theorems on set theory.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:52):
The difference between type theory and set theory is that in type theory, the only sets you can have are subsets of a fixed set. It took me a long time to realise that mathematicians use the concept of set in two different ways.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:53):
It could easily be a theorem in core Lean. Kenny is just trolling. He seems to have caused you a great deal of confusion. There is nothing special about lines.ext
. You will have to prove lots of theorems.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:53):
The point is that if you make a new definition (e.g. lines
) then you will have to prove lots of theorems about that definition.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:55):
Oh I see. And yes, I'm becoming more confused the more I learn. This is fine, though!
import tactic local attribute [instance, priority 0] classical.prop_decidable noncomputable theory open_locale classical universe u constant Points : Type u constant Lines : set (set Points) constant I1 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃! ℓ : Lines, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )
Why does Lean complain in the last line?
---- > I figured it out! Now Lines is a set :-)
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 13:55):
Take a look at the way Lean does complex numbers. A new definition, and then immediately you have to prove a bunch of trivial theorems about complex
. Lean might have lots of theorems about sets, but if you define lines
then you have to prove theorems about lines
including trivial theorems.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 13:57):
Take a look at the way Lean does complex numbers. A new definition, and then immediately you have to prove a bunch of trivial theorems about
complex
. Lean might have lots of theorems about sets, but if you definelines
then you have to prove theorems aboutlines
including trivial theorems.
I see. That will keep me busy.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 14:53):
This morning I sweated to prove (with help!)
lemma I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s : Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s
I modified it now to work with lines being sets of points:
lemma I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s ∈ Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s
But the proof I had stopped working. I am stuck at:
lemma I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s ∈ Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s := begin intros A B r s rL sL h hAr hBr hAs hBs, apply unique_of_exists_unique (I1 A B h), sorry, end
and I am trying to complete it using the fact that I1 is a lot stronger...
Moreover, I don't like that there are so many hypothesis. It seems that this is a side effect of working with sets.
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 15:07):
If you use variables
you can state some hypotheses just once at the beginning of a section
or namespace
. See 2.6 of Theorem Proving in Lean if you haven't already.
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 15:11):
Oh, I guess you may also want to state your lemma like this to avoid the giant intros
at the start of the proof:
lemma I12 {A B : Points} {r s : set Points} (rL : r ∈ Lines) (sL : s ∈ Lines) (h : A ≠ B) (hAr : A ∈ r) (hBr : B ∈ r) (hAs : A ∈ s) (hBs : B ∈ s) : r = s := sorry
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 15:15):
@Marc Masdeu At this point, if you really want to pursue the geometry formalisation (instead of just fooling around to learn more Lean), I think it would be useful to look at the previous attempts.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 15:19):
Marc Masdeu At this point, if you really want to pursue the geometry formalisation (instead of just fooling around to learn more Lean), I think it would be useful to look at the previous attempts.
Oh I do want to fool around. Formalizing geometry was just what I picked as a testing grounds, since it doesn't itself have much pre-requisites. Eventually I will want to teach students how to use this, so I better learn a bit first.
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 15:22):
Could you post what you have in its entirety? Otherwise I can only guess how you corrected I1
.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 15:23):
import tactic -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle local attribute [instance, priority 0] classical.prop_decidable noncomputable theory open_locale classical universe u constant Points : Type u constant Lines : set(set(Points)) constant I1 : ∀ A B : Points, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) constant I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Points, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ constant I3 : ∃ A B C : Points, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) ))) notation p `xor` q := (p ∧ ¬ q) ∨ (q ∧ ¬ p) lemma I12 : ∀ A B : Points, ∀ r s ∈ Lines, (A ≠ B) → (A ∈ r) → (B ∈ r) → (A ∈ s) → (B ∈ s) → r = s := begin intros A B r s rL sL h hAr hBr hAs hBs, apply unique_of_exists_unique (I1 A B h), end
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 15:31):
Does open_locale classical
not automatically do the local attribute business? What happens if you delete line 3?
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 15:33):
I don't see any change. I copied line 3 from somewhere, and kept the comment since I do want to use the LEM.
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 15:40):
The unfold
s are unnecessary, but may help you see what's going on.
lemma I12 {A B : Points} {r s : set Points} (rL : r ∈ Lines) (sL : s ∈ Lines) (h : A ≠ B) (hAr : A ∈ r) (hBr : B ∈ r) (hAs : A ∈ s) (hBs : B ∈ s) : r = s := begin apply unique_of_exists_unique (I1 A B h), { unfold exists_unique, use rL, split, split, assumption, assumption, finish, }, { unfold exists_unique, use sL, split, split, assumption, assumption, finish, }, end
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 15:45):
Thanks! Now that we are at this. You changed a lot the definition of the lemma, by removing all the foralls, for example. What is the difference between the two, and which form should I prefer? The form that I had was a bit similar to what I would do in math, and this notation breaks the symmetry between forall and exists, right?
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 15:52):
@Bryan Gin-ge Chen I don't understand what did the finish
do...
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 16:06):
At a mathematical level they're equivalent. There are slight differences when it comes to how Lean interprets them due to the fact that I made A
, B
, r
and s
"implicit arguments" using curly braces.
In Lean what I wrote is generally preferred since it saves a lot of typing. (Using variables
would be even better). Could you say more about the symmetry you expect between forall and exists?
finish
is a tactic which is able to clear "obvious" goals if they just boil down to logical manipulation. In this case, it turns out that you can just as well use intros, refl
instead of finish
.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 16:11):
Could you say more about the symmetry you expect between forall and exists?
Well, how would you write in Lean these two statements (which I see as "symmetrical"):
for all x, P(x)
and there exists x, P(x)
.
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 16:13):
I'd write them like this: ∀ x, P x
, ∃ x, P x
. They behave rather differently though.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 16:15):
They are yin and yang
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 16:18):
"forall x" indicates to me that the thing that follows is a function of x. (It just happens to take values in the world of logical propositions). Lean lets us write such statements using more function-oriented syntax (we can give x as an argument to the function).
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 16:18):
Yes, that's the symmetry that I meant! But you see, if you want to write a lemma one could write:
lemma hasP : \forall x : Type, P x
or lemma existsP : \exists x : Type, P x
. The first one can be rewritten as
lemma hasP {x : Type} : P x
. What about the second?
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 16:18):
You can't move the exists to the left of the colon. They are different in that respect.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 16:19):
The general concept of "negation" switches them around
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 16:20):
You can't move the exists to the left of the colon. They are different in that respect.
I think that this is what I was observing. I guess one gets used to it.
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 16:20):
I guess this constructive logic leaking through....
Johan Commelin (Jan 15 2020 at 16:20):
Because there they aren't symmetric at all.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 16:29):
They are like night and day. "I can see in the day, how come I can't see in the night?"
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 15 2020 at 16:30):
Since forall gives rise to functions maybe exists should arise from co-functions (in the sense of "co-data"?)...
Chris Hughes (Jan 15 2020 at 16:31):
It is a coproduct.
Chris Hughes (Jan 15 2020 at 16:31):
And functions are products.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 15 2020 at 17:45):
@Marc Masdeu -- here's the difference between sets and types. If a mathematician says "let G be a group and let S be a set, and imagine G acts on S, blah blah blah..." then they don't actually mean this, because imagine the chaos that would ensue if a random element of G (which is just a random set) turned out to coincidentally be an element of S, or a subset of S, or something? You could imagine that this would be irritating -- or just a bit weird. We don't say "assume moreover that G and S are disjoint" though, because sometimes we might well want to set G = S. What is happening is that we want elements of G to be "things of type G" and elements of S to be "things of type S" and we know that even if there were some random sets which happened to be in G and in S by accident, it won't matter, because as long as we know what we're doing, and we call them g if they're in G and s if they're in S, we can "pretend they're different".
This is why you want points to be a type, because a point will always be "a thing which is a point", you'll never use a point to do anything else other than being a point. Computer scientists say "a thing of type Point" for "a thing which is a point".
On the other hand, you absolutely want to allow lines to contain a common point, and this is a natural part of the theory. So you don't want lines to be types, you want them to be subsets, or possibly subtypes, of the type of points.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 15 2020 at 18:05):
@Kevin Buzzard thanks for the very nice explanation. We usually don't think about this, and it's surprising how long one can be doing maths without ever having this clarified.
Vaibhav Karve (Jan 16 2020 at 22:56):
The difference between type theory and set theory is that in type theory, the only sets you can have are subsets of a fixed set. It took me a long time to realise that mathematicians use the concept of set in two different ways.
@Kevin Buzzard Can you elaborate on that? Things that obey ZFC is one way i can think of. What's the other?
Mario Carneiro (Jan 16 2020 at 23:03):
There are sets, and then there are subsets. These are treated in the same way by ZFC
Mario Carneiro (Jan 16 2020 at 23:06):
Sometimes, you just talk about an arbitrary set taken from the universe of all sets. These are like types in type theory. Other times you have a set that lives in another set, for example an open set in a topology. These admit a reasonable notion of intersection, complement, and other such things, and they are represented by elements of the type set A
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:19):
OK back to Hilbert's axioms. I have introduced a few more axioms and proved some more basic lemmas about them. The file is getting long and Lean takes time to react after each small change, so I decide to reorganize things a bit.
- Is it possible to "input" (in the LaTeX terminology) a file, so that Lean just inserts the content of that file at the beginning?
A better way would be to start writing a structure, and this is the route I'd like to take (mainly for the sake of learning how to do it). So I have:
import tactic noncomputable theory -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle open_locale classical universe u structure HilbertPlane (Point : Type u) := (Lines : set(set(Point))) (lies_on : Point → Lines → Prop) (I1 : ∀ A B : Point, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )) (I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Point, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) (I3 : ∃ A B C : Point, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) )))) (between : Point → Point → Point → Prop)
and Lean seems happy so far. But for the next axioms I want to have some notation. In the previous version I had something like
notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C definition colinear (A B C : Point) := ∃ ℓ ∈ HilbertPlane.Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ
but now both lines fail. I assume that this gets me out of the structure, but I would really like to have such notation inside to be able to both state the axioms in a more readable way, and also in order to be able to use the HilbertPlane structure in an easy way later when writing theorems.
How is this done in Lean (I looked at @Ali Sever solution and in the list of axioms there is no notation being added...).
Thanks!
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 17 2020 at 11:26):
import
= input
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 17 2020 at 11:28):
Marc -- if you want to get confused about imports, take a look at my lecture for today
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:32):
Marc -- if you want to get confused about imports, take a look at my lecture for today
I thought that import was more like \include. In particular, if I split a file into two files (foo.lean and bar.lean) and put import foo
in bar.lean I get complaints all over.
Johan Commelin (Jan 17 2020 at 11:33):
@Marc Masdeu You can use import
, but you will have to reopen namespaces and such
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:35):
I thought @Kevin Buzzard and @Johan Commelin would tell me to definitely pursue my second option (structures). Is it that it it's not so easy to do what I wanted?
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:36):
You can do the notation in the middle of defining the structure by enclosing it in parentheses, like so:
structure HilbertPlane (Point : Type u) := (Lines : set(set(Point))) (lies_on : Point → Lines → Prop) (I1 : ∀ A B : Point, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )) (I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Point, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) (I3 : ∃ A B C : Point, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) )))) (between : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C)
The definition is however not so easy
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:37):
You could make it another part of the structure, but then it isn't guaranteed to have the definition you want and you have to impose that separately
Johan Commelin (Jan 17 2020 at 11:37):
Concerning using notation
in the definition of a structure: See how it's done for categories a long time ago: https://github.com/leanprover-community/mathlib/blob/c06fb67cf8b7bcc3e5e76c46b699d01cd4c212a6/src/category_theory/category.lean#L46L54
Johan Commelin (Jan 17 2020 at 11:38):
Aha, Mario beat me.
Johan Commelin (Jan 17 2020 at 11:38):
You have to restate the notation after the definition if you want it to exist outside the structure definition
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:40):
Otherwise, you have to define the structure in two stages, like so:
structure PreHilbertPlane (Point : Type u) := (Lines : set(set(Point))) (lies_on : Point → Lines → Prop) (I1 : ∀ A B : Point, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )) (I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Point, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) (I3 : ∃ A B C : Point, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) )))) (between : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C) definition colinear {Point} (Ω : PreHilbertPlane Point) (A B C : Point) := ∃ ℓ ∈ Ω.Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ structure HilbertPlane (Point : Type u) extends PreHilbertPlane Point := (notation `colinear` := colinear to_PreHilbertPlane) (foo : ∀ a, colinear a a a) (etc : ...)
Johan Commelin (Jan 17 2020 at 11:43):
How about extending the code that Kenny built in the other thread?
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:49):
That code has lots of things that I don't understand: class, instance, @[...], ... Also, the set of axioms is different. There are several formalizations of geometry, what I am trying to do is: take Hartshorne's UTM book and translate some chapters into Lean. I'd like to do this in the most straightforward way: ideally, you should be able to translate clear pen-and-paper thoughts into Lean, not having to re-think them. So if at some point he introduces a definition, I'd like to do so at the same point, etcetera.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:49):
@Mario Carneiro Is that Lean-Kosher and not a hack? I want to think about between
and colinear
in a very similar way. One is an undefined property that 3 points can have, whereas the other is a defined property.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:50):
The way I wrote it in the last code snippet, it is a defined property
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:52):
The version with it being an undefined property with a characterization looks like this:
structure HilbertPlane (Point : Type u) := (Lines : set(set(Point))) (lies_on : Point → Lines → Prop) (I1 : ∀ A B : Point, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )) (I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Point, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) (I3 : ∃ A B C : Point, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) )))) (between : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C) (colinear : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (colinear_def : ∀ A B C, colinear A B C ↔ ∃ ℓ ∈ Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ) (etc : ...)
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:54):
The way I wrote it in the last code snippet, it is a defined property
Yes, I meant that the way between
and colinear
are introduced in the code is very different (and also now I have an extra structure, which may be useful but requires changing the layout I had initially)...
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 11:56):
@Mario Carneiro Oh! So the last code snippet does work? This is exactly what I was looking for.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:57):
There is a third option, which is to have colinear
be a (large) notation in the definition, resulting in complicated axioms, but then pick up the pieces afterward
structure HilbertPlane (Point : Type u) := (Lines : set(set(Point))) (lies_on : Point → Lines → Prop) (I1 : ∀ A B : Point, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )) (I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Point, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) (I3 : ∃ A B C : Point, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) )))) (between : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C) (notation `colinear` := λ A B C : Point, ∃ ℓ ∈ Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ) (foo : ∀ a, colinear a a a) def colinear {Point} (Ω : HilbertPlane Point) (A B C : Point) := ∃ ℓ ∈ Ω.Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ theorem HilbertPlane.foo' {Point} (Ω : HilbertPlane Point) : ∀ a, colinear Ω a a a := HilbertPlane.foo _
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 11:59):
Note that the actual type of HilbertPlane.foo
here is:
#print HilbertPlane.foo -- def HilbertPlane.foo : ∀ {Point : Type u} (c : HilbertPlane Point) (a : Point), -- (λ (A B C : Point), ∃ (ℓ : set Point) (H : ℓ ∈ c.Lines), A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ) a a a
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 12:03):
There are several formalizations of geometry, what I am trying to do is: take Hartshorne's UTM book and translate some chapters into Lean. I'd like to do this in the most straightforward way: ideally, you should be able to translate clear pen-and-paper thoughts into Lean, not having to re-think them. So if at some point he introduces a definition, I'd like to do so at the same point, etcetera.
Sadly, this approach generally doesn't work out in the long term. Trying to stick too closely to a mathematical presentation can make your job harder than it already is
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 12:04):
Using a math text as a guide is a good idea, but expect to have to make small modifications frequently
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 12:07):
Sadly, this approach generally doesn't work out in the long term. Trying to stick too closely to a mathematical presentation can make your job harder than it already is
I agree with you that if you want to make such code available to others it is best to think carefully on design so that you don't run into problems later. My goal is different: I am trying to learn Lean "as a user", and one way is to see how everything that a book (or myself) would want to put in a paper can be translated. Same happens when you program: writing a library / module is very different than translating an idea you have for an algorithm into python, say.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 12:12):
I think what you are doing is a valuable way to learn, and a math text is a good starting point. I'm just saying that you shouldn't be afraid to make modifications in service of easier formalization
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 12:13):
which is itself important for learning how to write "lean idioms", things that work with the theorem prover rather than against it
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 12:15):
Completely agree. When I learned Python, the code that I wrote looked a lot like what I would have written in C. The more I learned, the more Python slang I could fluently speak and then I started thinking of my algorithms in a more pythonic way. I am at the first stage with Lean.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 17 2020 at 12:16):
While I am not saying you should just pick up Kenny's code, it does have a lot of idioms in it that could be useful for you
Marc Masdeu (Jan 17 2020 at 12:36):
I am trying to understand what's in there, but I find it hard (I don't yet know enough Lean language).
Sebastien Gouezel (Jan 17 2020 at 12:56):
colinear or collinear?
Marc Masdeu (Jan 20 2020 at 12:07):
I have put the definitions into a class, split the code into two files and I am running into more problems.
- I learned that I couldn't put the definitions in
axioms.lean
because then things broke. I changed the file name intohpdefs.lean
and suddenly it worked. This was utterly frustrating, is there a simple explanation? - I don't now how to use the notations that I defined in the class I made, in another file.
This is my code so far:
hpdefs.lean file:
import tactic namespace hilbertplane noncomputable theory -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle open_locale classical universe u notation p `xor` q := (p ∧ ¬ q) ∨ (q ∧ ¬ p) class HilbertPlane:= (Point : Type u) (Lines : set(set(Point))) (I1 : ∀ A B : Point, A ≠ B → ∃! (ℓ ∈ Lines), ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ )) (I2 : ∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, ∃ A B : Point, A ≠ B ∧ A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) (I3 : ∃ A B C : Point, (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ (∀ ℓ ∈ Lines, (A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ) → (¬ (C ∈ ℓ) )))) (between : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (notation A `*` B `*` C := between A B C) (collinear : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (collinear_def : ∀ A B C, collinear A B C ↔ ∃ ℓ ∈ Lines, A ∈ ℓ ∧ B ∈ ℓ ∧ C ∈ ℓ) (noncollinear : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (noncollinear_def : ∀ A B C, noncollinear A B C ↔ ¬ collinear A B C) (B11 (A B C : Point) : (A * B * C) → (C * B * A)) (B12 (A B C : Point) : (A * B * C) → (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ collinear A B C)) (B2 (A B : Point) : ∃ C, A * B * C) (B3 (A B C : Point) {ℓ ∈ Lines} (hAB : A ≠ B) (hAC : A ≠ C) (hBC : B ≠ C) (hAl : A ∈ ℓ) (hBl : B ∈ ℓ) (hCl : C ∈ ℓ) : ((A * B * C) ∧ ¬( B * A * C ) ∧ ¬ (A * C * B)) ∨ (¬ (A * B * C) ∧ ( B * A * C ) ∧ ¬ (A * C * B)) ∨ (¬ (A * B * C) ∧ ¬( B * A * C ) ∧ (A * C * B))) (B4 (A B C D: Point) {ℓ ∈ Lines} (hnc: noncollinear A B C) (hnAl: ¬ (A ∈ ℓ)) (hnBl: ¬ B ∈ ℓ) (hnCl: ¬ C ∈ ℓ) (hDl: D ∈ ℓ) (hADB: A * D * B) : (∃ E : Point, (A * E * C) xor (B * E * C))) (intersect : set Point → set Point → Prop) (intersect_def (r s : set(Point)) : (intersect r s ↔ ∃ A : Point, A ∈ r ∧ A ∈ s)) (parallel : set Point → set Point → Prop) (parallel_def (r s : set Point) : parallel r s ↔ r ∈ Lines ∧ s ∈ Lines → (r = s) ∨ (¬ (intersect r s))) (notation r `||` s := parallel r s) (parallel_postulate {A : Point} {ℓ r s : set Point} (h1 : ℓ ∈ Lines) (hr : r ∈ Lines) (hs : s ∈ Lines) : A ∈ r ∧ A ∈ s ∧ r || ℓ ∧ s || ℓ → r = s) (line_segment (A B : Point) : set Point := {A} ∪ {B} ∪ {C | A * C * B}) (notation A `#` B := line_segment A B) (triangle (A B C : Point) (h: noncollinear A B C) : set Point := (A#B) ∪ (A#C) ∪ (B#C)) end hilbertplane
firstlemmas.lean
import .hpdefs open hilbertplane variables {Ω : HilbertPlane} variables {A B C: Ω.Point} variables {ℓ r s : set(Ω.Point)} lemma I11 : ∀ A B, A ≠ B → ∃ ℓ ∈ Ω.Lines, ( A ∈ ℓ ) ∧ ( B ∈ ℓ ) := begin intros A B, intro h, cases HilbertPlane.I1 A B h with ℓ h1, existsi ℓ, cases h1 with H, exact exists_of_exists_unique H, end lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Ω.Point) : A ∈ A#B ∧ B ∈ A#B := begin split; { unfold line_segment, finish, } end
and the lemma endpoints_are_in_segment
bothers Lean because it doesn't understand the #
notation. Any pointers? Thank you.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 20 2020 at 12:40):
The filename thing sounds mysterious. Could you describe more precisely what you did and what happened?
Mario Carneiro (Jan 20 2020 at 12:42):
One possibility that comes to mind is that axioms
is a keyword, so if you write import axioms
it will import nothing and then start declaring axioms
Mario Carneiro (Jan 20 2020 at 12:45):
If you really want to call the file axioms.lean
, you can import it using french quote escapes: import «axioms»
Mario Carneiro (Jan 20 2020 at 12:46):
As for notations, you have to redeclare all the notations outside the structure because they are scoped to the structure definition itself
Marc Masdeu (Jan 20 2020 at 13:07):
The filename thing sounds mysterious. Could you describe more precisely what you did and what happened?
Rename the file hpdefs.lean
into axioms.lean
. Then in firstlemmas.lean
have the first line import .axioms
and Lean complains. But your explanation is reasonable. I will avoid this file name in the future.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 22 2020 at 08:48):
OK, I got stuck again. I don't see why the following code does not work:
import tactic noncomputable theory -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle open_locale classical universe u class HilbertPlane:= (Point : Type u) (Lines : set(set(Point))) (line_segment : Point → Point → set Point) (line_segment_def (A B : Point) : line_segment A B = {A} ∪ {B}) constant Ω : HilbertPlane lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Ω.Point) : (A ∈ (Ω.line_segment A B)) := begin sorry, end
It is frustrating, since this works perfectly:
import tactic noncomputable theory -- We want to be able to define functions using the law of excluded middle open_locale classical universe u constant Point : Type u constant Lines : set(set(Point)) definition line_segment (A B : Point) : set Point := {A} ∪ {B} lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Point) : (A ∈ line_segment A B) := begin unfold line_segment, finish, end
Apart from the solution, I would appreciate being able to tell in the future how to fix these issues (by reading at errors, or using "debugging" commands in Lean). I hope I didn't have to constantly ask Zulip...
Mario Carneiro (Jan 22 2020 at 09:04):
Let's start with the error message.
invalid field notation, function 'HilbertPlane.line_segment' does not have explicit argument with type (HilbertPlane ...)
Okay, that's weird. What type does it actually have?
#print HilbertPlane.line_segment
@[reducible] def HilbertPlane.line_segment : Π [c : HilbertPlane], HilbertPlane.Point → HilbertPlane.Point → set HilbertPlane.Point := λ [c : HilbertPlane], [HilbertPlane.line_segment c]
Notice that c
here, the HilbertPlane
argument in question, is in square brackets. That means it is intended to be inferred by type class inference. Why? Because you called HilbertPlane
a class
rather than a structure
.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 22 2020 at 09:13):
The idea with typeclass arguments is that you don't specify them, you let lean figure them out. Let's try that:
lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Ω.Point) : (A ∈ (line_segment A B)) := sorry
unknown identifier 'line_segment'
Thanks lean. Guess we need to open the namespace
open HilbertPlane lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Ω.Point) : (A ∈ (line_segment A B)) := sorry
failed to synthesize type class instance for A : Point, B : Point ⊢ HilbertPlane
Okay, getting closer. It says it can't find an instance of HilbertPlane
. (Notice also that it omits the Ω
in Point
. Clearly that's how it expects you to write it.) I will note at this point that HilbertPlane
has no arguments, which is rather unusual for a typeclass. It's really only a useful construct if there is only ever one HilbertPlane
around, but maybe that's the case for you.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 22 2020 at 09:13):
In any case, we can add it as an instance variable, and then lean should find it:
variable [HilbertPlane] open HilbertPlane lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Point) : (A ∈ (line_segment A B)) := sorry
kernel failed to type check declaration 'endpoints_are_in_segment' this is usually due to a buggy tactic or a bug in the builtin elaborator elaborated type: ∀ [_inst_1 : HilbertPlane] (A B : Point), A ∈ line_segment A B elaborated value: λ [_inst_1 : HilbertPlane] (A B : Point), sorry nested exception message: invalid reference to undefined universe level parameter 'u_1'
Ooh, these are extra special errors that you get if you managed to fool the tactic framework into producing an invalid proof. I think this will go away if you actually finish the proof, though.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 22 2020 at 09:18):
variable [HilbertPlane] open HilbertPlane lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Point) : (A ∈ (line_segment A B)) := by simp [line_segment_def]
kernel failed to type check declaration 'endpoints_are_in_segment' this is usually due to a buggy tactic or a bug in the builtin elaborator elaborated type: ∀ [_inst_1 : HilbertPlane] (A B : Point), A ∈ line_segment A B elaborated value: λ [_inst_1 : HilbertPlane] (A B : Point), eq.mpr ... trivial nested exception message: invalid reference to undefined universe level parameter 'u_1'
Apparently my hope was unfounded. This is an actual bug in lean, so I'm not sure what the best workaround is, but explicitly including the instance seems to work:
variable [Ω : HilbertPlane] include Ω open HilbertPlane lemma endpoints_are_in_segment (A B : Point) : (A ∈ (line_segment A B)) := by simp [line_segment_def] -- works
Marc Masdeu (Jan 22 2020 at 09:42):
Oh wow! This is a great explanation!! I will see if I can fit this into the rest of the code. Still, I doubt I'd be able to debug something like this in the future. Lean is hard.
Patrick Massot (Jan 22 2020 at 10:45):
I really don't see the point of having a type class with no argument. Why don't you make the type of points a parameter of HilbertPlane
? This would be useful if you want to extend to three-dimensional geometry. Then you'll have subtypes having a HilbertPlane
structure.
Mario Carneiro (Jan 22 2020 at 11:52):
@Patrick Massot One reason you might not want to use HilbertPlane P
where P
is the type of points is that there are also lines to deal with. Would you write Lines P
for that type?
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 22 2020 at 13:01):
Oh wow! This is a great explanation!! I will see if I can fit this into the rest of the code. Still, I doubt I'd be able to debug something like this in the future. Lean is hard.
Algebraic number theory is hard. There's a learning curve. I couldn't do my first year example sheets for a long time. Working on them taught me basic logic, then defining schemes taught me about classes and structures, and then I learnt how to read the error messages, and now I can usually solve problems myself. The way to learn it is to do exactly what you're doing -- try some maths at a level which is suitable for your current formalisation skills and ask when you get stuck, then repeat
Marc Masdeu (Jan 22 2020 at 15:15):
@Mario Carneiro and @Patrick Massot I will probably deal with these issues later...
Marc Masdeu (Jan 22 2020 at 15:17):
Now I have a file hpdefs.lean
and a file lesson1.lean
, this second one with some lemmas that seem to compile (I'm still using CoCalc for this). I want to start a new file, lesson2.lean
. I type this into the new file:
import .lesson1 open hilbertplane variables {Ω : HilbertPlane}
and it already complains that "imported file '/home/user/leanprojects/test/src/lesson1.lean' uses sorry" (which I can't see in that file). So what does that error message mean actually?
Patrick Massot (Jan 22 2020 at 15:18):
The sorry may be in a file imported by lesson1
Marc Masdeu (Jan 22 2020 at 15:20):
lesson1 only imports hpdefs, which has no sorry's either...
Marc Masdeu (Jan 22 2020 at 15:26):
It turns out that cocalc had issues with some sort of caching. I restarted everything and the complaint went away... Thanks @Patrick Massot !
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 09:29):
This question should be quick: I have the state:
Ω : HilbertPlane, A : HilbertPlane.Point ⊢ {C : HilbertPlane.Point | A * C*A} = ∅
This is a trivial statement, directly following from the axiom:
(B12 (A B C : Point) : (A * B * C) → (A ≠ B ∧ A ≠ C ∧ B ≠ C ∧ collinear A B C))
but I don't see how to do it in Lean. I would like to say to Lean:
1) Let C be a point in the left set.
2) By B12 A B A we have A \neq A, contradiction.
Patrick Massot (Jan 23 2020 at 09:36):
A generic start would be ext C, suffices : ¬ A*C*A, by simpa,
.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 09:39):
The ext C is what I didn't know...
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 09:56):
I then intro'd h : A * C * A
I want to apply B12's second inequality (one of the 4 and statements). I suceeded with
have g := (HilbertPlane.B12 A C A) h, finish,
:grinning:
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 10:41):
It's clear how to proceed here:
Tactic State Ω : HilbertPlane, A : HilbertPlane.Point, ℓ : set HilbertPlane.Point, h : A ∉ ℓ ⊢ {A} ∩ ℓ = ∅
I even found something called set.inter_singleton_eq_empty
, which looks like would finish this instantly. But I don't now how to apply it.
It's clear that this is not the most direct way:
ext C, split, { intro h, exfalso, cases h with h3 h4, finish, }, simp,
How could I do easier? On a related note, if I managed to prove a statement in some sort of convoluted way (like above), can I ask Lean to give me a proof that I can paste back to avoid using complicated tactics?
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 11:11):
@Marc Masdeu That name reads like the singleton is on the right hand side of ∩
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 11:11):
Is there also set.singleton_inter_eq_empty
?
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 11:11):
Otherwise, maybe rw set.inter_comm
?
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 11:11):
(I just made up that name, but it should exist.)
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 11:12):
Also squeeze_simp [h]
might be able to help
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 11:15):
Otherwise, maybe
rw set.inter_comm
?
This worked! So I finished it with:
rw set.inter_comm, rw set.inter_singleton_eq_empty, exact h1,
Great!
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 11:36):
@Marc Masdeu Does this mean that set.singleton_inter_eq_empty
is missing? If so, that's a (tiny) hole in the library
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 11:54):
It does exist, and it clears the goal in one less line :-).
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 12:06):
I guess you could save another line if you don't rw
but exact
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 12:08):
@Marc Masdeu Do you know about suggest
?
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 12:08):
I guess if you type suggest
for your initial problem, it would tell you how to close the goal in 1 line.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 12:10):
Marc Masdeu Do you know about
suggest
?
Oh no, I didn't know about this one! I am getting a bit mixed up with suggest
, simp
, simpa
, finish
, cc
and so on...
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 12:10):
Haha, I can imagine
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 12:11):
suggest
is extremely useful.
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 12:11):
So useful that I wish there was a dedicated window showing its results, without having to type it myself.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 12:13):
Now that I have you here, do you know of an analogue for rcases to deal with
h : p \and q \and r \and s
I would like to do something like split_h into \langle h1, h2, h3, h4 \rangle
. Instead, i do:
have hAB := h1.left, have h2 := h1.right, have hAC := h2.left, have h3 := h2.right, have hBC := h3.left, have h4 := h3.right,
Reid Barton (Jan 23 2020 at 12:14):
That's what rcases
does
Reid Barton (Jan 23 2020 at 12:14):
split_h into
-> rcases h with
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 12:16):
Oh, I just tried and it did work. I am realising that it works in different settings (I had just used it in \exists A B C...
type statements)
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 12:17):
So useful that I wish there was a dedicated window showing its results, without having to type it myself.
I haven't managed to use suggest
from CoCalc. Is this a VSCode feature?
Reid Barton (Jan 23 2020 at 12:18):
Ah yes. rcases works on any inductive type, including equality, and I think also quotients
Johan Commelin (Jan 23 2020 at 13:52):
So useful that I wish there was a dedicated window showing its results, without having to type it myself.
I haven't managed to use
suggest
from CoCalc. Is this a VSCode feature?
@Marc Masdeu No, it's pure mathlib. But it's not that old. So maybe CoCalc is using an old version of mathlib? Did you install it yourself on CoCalc, or are you using the mathlib that is available by default? (That one might be >1yr old.)
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 15:37):
Marc Masdeu No, it's pure mathlib. But it's not that old. So maybe CoCalc is using an old version of mathlib? Did you install it yourself on CoCalc, or are you using the mathlib that is available by default? (That one might be >1yr old.)
I just cloned the newest version, put it in CoCalc and it doesn't work. Do I have to open any particular namespace? It doesn't recognize it.
Reid Barton (Jan 23 2020 at 15:40):
Oh, you need import tactic.suggest
Bryan Gin-ge Chen (Jan 23 2020 at 15:52):
Either import tactic.basic
or import tactic
should work too.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 23 2020 at 16:00):
also with cocalc you have to know that its Lean is reading the leanpkg.path
in the root directory of the project as opposed to any other one in any other directory.
Marc Masdeu (Jan 23 2020 at 16:17):
Haven't succeeded yet... I checked that I was using the right mathlib version by changing the folder and then failing to import anything. I changed the folder back. @Kevin Buzzard Yes, I did know that I have no control over where Lean takes its files from.
Kevin Buzzard (Jan 23 2020 at 16:27):
you have control, it's just that you basically have one piece of control per cocalc project (and if you have one paid cocalc project with many lean projects in then it can get messy)
Julien Narboux (Mar 02 2020 at 20:27):
@Kevin Buzzard our formalization of Hilbert's geometry, use just a type for lines. In fact, I think we did not need sets at all to formalize Hilbert's geometry. Our axioms are here:
https://github.com/GeoCoq/GeoCoq/blob/master/Axioms/hilbert_axioms.v
Julien Narboux (Mar 02 2020 at 20:28):
We proved that those axioms are mutually interpretable with those of Tarski, so the formalization is ok in this sense.
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 20:36):
What do you gain by explicitly embedding all those decidability assumption instead of just using classical reasoning everywhere in the library? I would understand the idea of delimiting results that are classically valid, but those assumption are there at the very bottom of the hierarchy, right?
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 20:38):
I would also be curious to know why you don't introduce notations like A ∈ L
for IncidL A L
. There is no risk of being misled by notations instead of following the rules since Coq is checking everything.
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 20:46):
I can't read two_points_on_line : forall l, { A : Point & { B | IncidL B l /\ IncidL A l /\ A <> B}}
. I understand it says each lines contains at least two distinct points, but I don't understand the way it is stated. What is the syntax here?
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 20:53):
For people interested in GeoCoq, here the regex translation Coq -> Lean of the first class in Julien's file (modulo the strange syntax that I translated using my maths intuition without understanding the Coq syntax).
class Hilbert_neutral_dimensionless := (Point : Type) (Line : Type) (Plane : Type) (EqL : Line → Line → Prop) (EqL_Equiv : equivalence EqL) (EqP : Plane → Plane → Prop) (EqP_Equiv : equivalence EqP) (IncidL : Point → Line → Prop) (IncidP : Point → Plane → Prop) (IncidL_morphism : ∀ P l m, IncidL P l → EqL l m → IncidL P m) (IncidL_dec : ∀ P l, IncidL P l ∨ ¬ IncidL P l) (IncidP_morphism : ∀ M p q, IncidP M p → EqP p q → IncidP M q) (IncidP_dec : ∀ M p, IncidP M p ∨ ¬ IncidP M p) (eq_dec_pointsH : ∀ A B : Point, A=B ∨ ¬ A=B) /- Group I Incidence -/ (line_existence : ∀ A B, A ≠ B → ∃ l, IncidL A l ∧ IncidL B l) (line_uniqueness : ∀ A B l m, A ≠ B → IncidL A l → IncidL B l → IncidL A m → IncidL B m → EqL l m) (two_points_on_line : ∀ l, ∃ A B : Point, IncidL B l ∧ IncidL A l ∧ A ≠ B) (ColH := fun A B C, ∃ l, IncidL A l ∧ IncidL B l ∧ IncidL C l) (PP : Point) (PQ : Point) (PR : Point) (lower_dim_2 : PP ≠ PQ ∧ PQ ≠ PR ∧ PP ≠ PR ∧ ¬ ColH PP PQ PR) (plane_existence : ∀ A B C, ¬ ColH A B C → ∃ p, IncidP A p ∧ IncidP B p ∧ IncidP C p) (one_point_on_plane : ∀ p, ∃ A, IncidP A p) (plane_uniqueness : ∀ A B C p q, ¬ ColH A B C → IncidP A p → IncidP B p → IncidP C p → IncidP A q → IncidP B q → IncidP C q → EqP p q) (IncidLP := fun l p, ∀ A, IncidL A l → IncidP A p) (line_on_plane : ∀ A B l p, A ≠ B → IncidL A l → IncidL B l → IncidP A p → IncidP B p → IncidLP l p) /- Group II Order -/ (BetH : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (between_diff : ∀ A B C, BetH A B C → A ≠ C) (between_col : ∀ A B C, BetH A B C → ColH A B C) (between_comm : ∀ A B C, BetH A B C → BetH C B A) (between_out : ∀ A B, A ≠ B → ∃ C, BetH A B C) (between_only_one : ∀ A B C, BetH A B C → ¬ BetH B C A) (cut := fun l A B , ¬ IncidL A l ∧ ¬ IncidL B l ∧ ∃ I, IncidL I l ∧ BetH A I B) (pasch : ∀ A B C l p, ¬ ColH A B C → IncidP A p → IncidP B p → IncidP C p → IncidLP l p → ¬ IncidL C l → cut l A B → cut l A C ∨ cut l B C) /- Group III Congruence -/ (CongH : Point → Point → Point → Point → Prop) (cong_permr : ∀ A B C D, CongH A B C D → CongH A B D C) (outH := fun P A B, BetH P A B ∨ BetH P B A ∨ (P ≠ A ∧ A = B)) (cong_existence : ∀ A B A' P l, A ≠ B → A' ≠ P → IncidL A' l → IncidL P l → ∃ B', IncidL B' l ∧ outH A' P B' ∧ CongH A' B' A B) (cong_pseudo_transitivity : ∀ A B C D E F, CongH A B C D → CongH A B E F → CongH C D E F) (disjoint := fun A B C D, ¬ ∃ P, BetH A P B ∧ BetH C P D) (addition : ∀ A B C A' B' C', ColH A B C → ColH A' B' C' → disjoint A B B C → disjoint A' B' B' C' → CongH A B A' B' → CongH B C B' C' → CongH A C A' C') (CongaH : Point → Point → Point → Point → Point → Point → Prop) (conga_refl : ∀ A B C, ¬ ColH A B C → CongaH A B C A B C) (conga_comm : ∀ A B C, ¬ ColH A B C → CongaH A B C C B A) (conga_permlr : ∀ A B C D E F, CongaH A B C D E F → CongaH C B A F E D) (same_side := fun A B l, ∃ P, cut l A P ∧ cut l B P) (same_side' := fun A B X Y, X ≠ Y ∧ ∀ l, IncidL X l → IncidL Y l → same_side A B l) (conga_out_conga : ∀ A B C D E F A' C' D' F', CongaH A B C D E F → outH B A A' → outH B C C' → outH E D D' → outH E F F' → CongaH A' B C' D' E F') (cong_4_existence : ∀ A B C O X P, ¬ ColH P O X → ¬ ColH A B C → ∃ Y, CongaH A B C X O Y ∧ same_side' P Y O X) (cong_4_uniqueness : ∀ A B C O P X Y Y', ¬ ColH P O X → ¬ ColH A B C → CongaH A B C X O Y → CongaH A B C X O Y' → same_side' P Y O X → same_side' P Y' O X → outH O Y Y') (cong_5 : ∀ A B C A' B' C', ¬ ColH A B C → ¬ ColH A' B' C' → CongH A B A' B' → CongH A C A' C' → CongaH B A C B' A' C' → CongaH A B C A' B' C')
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:00):
{ A : Point & ... }
is a dependent pair I think, like Σ (A : Point), ...
. After that comes a subtype.
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:13):
Thanks Reid. So this is again intuitionistic stuff.
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:21):
Those :=
lines don't work in lean the way I infer they work in coq
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:22):
Really?
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:22):
Oh yes
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:22):
I should have known what they do in Lean.
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:22):
How do we do that in Lean then?
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:22):
I'm actually kind of curious how this is supported in coq
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:22):
Introduce a notation only?
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:23):
you could do that, or you could add a field in the structure (possibly using :=
to give it the obvious default value) and then another field asserting equality to the required definition
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:24):
you won't get defeq of the field to its definition, although for an axiomatization like this it doesn't matter
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:38):
huh yeah, what is the type of ColH
in the coq version?
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:39):
Point -> Point -> Point -> Prop
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:39):
It says three point sit on the same line.
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:40):
But isn't it actually (T : Hilbert_neutral_dimensionless) -> T.Point -> T.Point -> T.Point -> Prop
or something?
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:40):
I think in coq that is actually a let binder in the middle of the structure
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:41):
which is not something you can do in lean
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:41):
but coq has support for let binders in the context, unlike lean, so that might be easier to support
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:42):
then does the type of plane_existence
for example have a let binder in it?
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:43):
In Hilbert_neutral_dimensionless.mk
, there is a let binder in the middle of the long string of arguments; in Hilbert_neutral_dimensionless.plane_existence
there is a reference to an external definition Hilbert_neutral_dimensionless.ColH
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:44):
or at least, that's how I would implement it
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:45):
but in lean if you tried that the kernel would unfold the let and in a definition this deep that could be a significant performance problem
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 21:47):
in coq they have "zeta reduction" which is Gamma, x : A := t |- x ~> t
, while in lean what I call zeta reduction is Gamma |- (let x : A := t in e) ~> e[t/x]
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:52):
sort of like lazy vs call-by-name evaluation?
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:53):
well, maybe not that much like it
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:54):
but somehow the work of substituting is delayed, I guess
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:57):
I've played the game of rewriting the beginning using notations (and getting rid of avoiding the equality sign):
class Hilbert_neutral_dimensionless := (Point : Type) (Line : Type) (Plane : Type) [IncidL : has_mem Point Line] [IncidP : has_mem Point Plane] /- Group I Incidence -/ (line_existence : ∀ A B, A ≠ B → ∃ l : Line, A ∈ l ∧ B ∈ l) (line_uniqueness : ∀ A B (l m : Line), A ≠ B → A ∈ l → B ∈ l → A ∈ m → B ∈ m → l = m) (two_points_on_line : ∀ l : Line, ∃ A B, B ∈ l ∧ A ∈ l ∧ A ≠ B) (notation `ColH⟮`A`, `B`, `C `⟯` := ∃ l : Line, A ∈ l ∧ B ∈ l ∧ C ∈ l) (PP : Point) (PQ : Point) (PR : Point) (lower_dim_2 : PP ≠ PQ ∧ PQ ≠ PR ∧ PP ≠ PR ∧ ¬ ColH⟮PP, PQ, PR⟯) (plane_existence : ∀ A B C, ¬ ColH⟮A, B, C⟯ → ∃ p : Plane, A ∈ p ∧ B ∈ p ∧ C ∈ p) (one_point_on_plane : ∀ p : Plane, ∃ A, A ∈ p) (plane_uniqueness : ∀ A B C (p q : Plane), ¬ ColH⟮A, B, C⟯ → A ∈ p → B ∈ p → C ∈ p → A ∈ q → B ∈ q → C ∈ q → p = q) (notation l `⊆` p := ∀ A, A ∈ (l : Line) → A ∈ (p : Plane)) (line_on_plane : ∀ A B l p, A ≠ B → A ∈ l → B ∈ l → A ∈ p → B ∈ p → l ⊆ p) /- Group II Order -/ (BetH : Point → Point → Point → Prop) (notation A `✶`:55 B:60 `✶`:55 C:60 := BetH A B C) (between_diff : ∀ A B C, A ✶ B ✶ C → A ≠ C) (between_col : ∀ A B C, A ✶ B ✶ C → ColH⟮A, B, C⟯) (between_comm : ∀ A B C, A ✶ B ✶ C → C ✶ B ✶ A) (between_out : ∀ A B, A ≠ B → ∃ C, A ✶ B ✶ C) (between_only_one : ∀ A B C, A ✶ B ✶ C → ¬ B ✶ C ✶ A) (notation `⟮`A `|`:55 l`|`:55 B `⟯` := ¬ A ∈ l ∧ ¬ B ∈ l ∧ ∃ I, I ∈ l ∧ A ✶ I ✶ B) -- cut: A and B are separated by l (pasch : ∀ A B C (l : Line) (p : Plane), ¬ ColH⟮A, B, C⟯ → A ∈ p → B ∈ p → C ∈ p → l ⊆ p → ¬ C ∈ l → ⟮A |l| B⟯ → ⟮A |l| C⟯ ∨ ⟮B |l| C⟯)
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 21:57):
the has_mem
fields threw me for a moment. Clever
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:58):
The down-side of this trick is it requires type annotations later on (otherwise Lean cannot tell what is a line and what is a plane).
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 21:59):
Julien, the relevant definitions here are:
class has_mem (α : Type u) (γ : Type v) := (mem : α → γ → Prop) infix ∈ := has_mem.mem
Patrick Massot (Mar 02 2020 at 22:01):
So every time Lean sees A ∈ P
and can infer the types of A
and P
are X
and Y
, it tries to solve the type class problem has_mem X Y
.
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 22:22):
My fonts don't know what you are using for ColH
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 22:22):
unless you actually are bordering the variables with boxes
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 22:23):
can't you just use regular brackets or braces there?
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 22:23):
unicode character combining red rectangle
Mario Carneiro (Mar 02 2020 at 22:24):
I want to react to this with an emoji that no font supports
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 22:25):
it's actually MATHEMATICAL LEFT FLATTENED PARENTHESIS
Reid Barton (Mar 02 2020 at 22:25):
but in my experience regular parentheses work fine in notation, yes
Kevin Buzzard (Mar 02 2020 at 22:30):
@Ali Sever sent me a README.md for his work, so at least now we can get some sort of an idea as to what he was doing.
Patrick Massot (Mar 03 2020 at 08:01):
About parenthesis: the key feature of the funny parentheses is there is no risk of confusion with other parenthesis so you don't need to understand the dark art of precedence settings. I'd love to see some really practical guide to setting precedences in our mathlib docs.
Last updated: Dec 20 2023 at 11:08 UTC