Zulip Chat Archive
Stream: general
Topic: Custom induction for def
Patrick Johnson (Apr 20 2022 at 12:17):
In Isabelle/HOL, for each definition there is an automatically generated induction principle. For example, if we define predicate even
recursively such that even 0
is true, even 1
is false and even (n+2)
is even n
for any natural number n
, then we get nat.two_step_induction
for free. Is there an equivalent in Lean?
Here is a simple example:
def P : ℕ → Prop
| 123 := true
| 45 := true
| _ := false
example {n : ℕ} (h : P n) : n = 123 ∨ n = 45 :=
begin
sorry
end
It would be nice if cases h
could split into two goals, one with n
replaced with 123
and the other with n
replaced with 45
. Is there such a tactic?
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 12:19):
If you defined P
as an inductive proposition then this would be the induction principle
Yaël Dillies (Apr 20 2022 at 12:19):
Probably you rather want
inductive P : ℕ → Prop
| intro123 : P 123
| intro45 : P 45
Then cases h
will do what you want.
Patrick Johnson (Apr 20 2022 at 12:26):
Sure, my example is bad. I am talking about re-using the recursion principle generated by the equation compiler, rather than proving it manually (like the even/odd example).
Patrick Johnson (Apr 20 2022 at 12:27):
So that we can use that principle when proving facts about the function.
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 12:27):
I don't understand the even/odd example because docs#nat.two_step_induction does not mention even
or odd
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 12:28):
But I guess the answer is that the equation compiler doesn't generate a recursion principle (for what?). It does generate equational lemmas.
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 12:32):
In Lean you can define an inductive family of propositions, in which case you get an induction principle that tells you all the ways that the proposition can be true. Or you can define a family of proposiitons by recursion on something else (like a nat
), which tells you how to "compute" the proposition for a specific natural number (by doing recursion on that number). They are different tools and in general it might not be straightforward to convert from one presentation to the other in an interesting way.
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 12:43):
For example if you define even
by recursion in Lean then it is basically the same as writing def even (n : nat) : Prop := nat.rec_on n true not
. There are no constants or axioms being added, and you could replace a usage of even
by this definition. I think it works quite differently in Isabelle/HOL.
Patrick Johnson (Apr 20 2022 at 12:54):
I am talking about this: suppose we define two functions f
and g
open nat
def f : ℕ → ℕ
| 0 := 0
| 1 := 0
| 2 := 0
| (succ (succ (succ n))) := f n
def g {α : Type} : list α → list α → list α
| [] ys := ys
| (x::xs) ys := have ys.length + xs.length < (x::xs).length + ys.length := sorry,
x :: g ys xs
using_well_founded { dec_tac := `[sorry] }
The equation compiler uses nat.rec
and list.rec
to build the functions. It would be nice if we could obtain the direct induction principle for the definition, rather than making a separate definition for it. For example, functions f
and g
would automatically generate
def f_rec {motive : ℕ → Sort*}
(f₀ : motive 0)
(f₁ : motive 1)
(f₂ : motive 2)
(fn : Π (n : ℕ), motive n → motive (succ (succ (succ n)))) :
Π (n : ℕ), motive n
| 0 := f₀
| 1 := f₁
| 2 := f₂
| (succ (succ (succ n))) := fn n (f_rec n)
def g_rec {α : Type} {motive : list α → list α → Sort*}
(g_nil : Π (ys : list α), motive [] ys)
(g_cons : Π (x : α) (xs ys : list α), motive ys xs → motive (x::xs) ys) :
Π (xs ys : list α), motive xs ys
| [] ys := g_nil ys
| (x::xs) ys := have ys.length + xs.length < (x::xs).length + ys.length := sorry,
g_cons x xs ys (g_rec ys xs)
using_well_founded { dec_tac := `[sorry] }
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 13:01):
OK, so basically the most general function with the same recursive structure as the original one. For example you can recover f
from f_rec
by f = f_rec 0 0 0 (\lam n x, x)
.
Patrick Johnson (Apr 20 2022 at 13:23):
If you defined
P
as an inductive proposition then this would be the induction principle.
We can't always do that. For example, this works:
def P : ℕ → Prop
| 0 := true
| (nat.succ n) := ¬P n
but this does not:
inductive P : ℕ → Prop
| zero : P 0
| succ {n : ℕ} : ¬P n → P n.succ
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 13:25):
Right, that's why the original question was so confusing :upside_down:
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 13:32):
What you want to do makes sense, for example (for some reason) you defined f
as above, and now you want to prove f n = 0
for all n
. I think the usual wisdom is something like:
- Avoid fancy recursive structures in the first place (not that common in math anyways, maybe more common in program verification)
- If you want to prove something about
f
(defined using the equation compiler) then you should use the equation compiler for the proof also. (Rather than yourf_rec
which would only be palatable if applied in tactic mode.) - Try to minimize the amount to which you need to do 1, e.g. by completely characterizing the behavior of
f
by a single lemma, so you don't need to reason by recursion aboutf
again and again.
Reid Barton (Apr 20 2022 at 13:47):
(For example even
is not actually defined by recursion in mathlib, it wouldn't occur to most mathematicians to define it that way, and I would go so far to say it would be a bad way to define it.)
Kyle Miller (Apr 20 2022 at 15:54):
@Reid Barton I remember someone asking about something like this last year, and the impression I got was that this is equivalent to having the equation compiler also define an inductive type that gives the underlying relation for the the function along with defining some lemma proving that the the relation is functional and is equivalent to the defined function. Then you can do induction on the function's recursion by doing induction on that relation.
I saw in the Lean 4 changelog that it's able to do induction on a recursion now, but I haven't looked into how you do that yet.
Kyle Miller (Apr 20 2022 at 15:55):
I think we could define such a type using a user attribute in Lean 3, where there'd be a constructor per equation lemma.
Last updated: Dec 20 2023 at 11:08 UTC