Zulip Chat Archive
Stream: new members
Topic: All decidable
Patrick Johnson (Dec 15 2021 at 07:56):
Is there a way to specify that everything I am working with in a lemma is decidable (prop_decidable
, decidable_pred
, nat.decidable_lt
, etc). I am facing weird situation where if I add letI := nat.decidable_lt
then the first half of the proof cannot unify, but if I remove it, then the second half of the proof cannot unify.
Patrick Johnson (Dec 15 2021 at 07:59):
BTW, I am totally confused about how decidability instances work :/
Eric Wieser (Dec 15 2021 at 08:03):
#mwe?
Patrick Johnson (Dec 15 2021 at 08:06):
import tactic
import data.list
open nat
open list
open classical
open_locale classical
def quicksort : list ℕ → list ℕ
| [] := []
| (x :: xs) :=
quicksort (filter (λy, y ≤ x) xs) ++
[x] ++
quicksort (filter (λy, x < y) xs)
using_well_founded { dec_tac := `[sorry] }
def sorted : list ℕ → Prop
| [] := true
| [x] := true
| (x :: y :: ys) := x ≤ y ∧ sorted (y :: ys)
lemma filter_length {f : ℕ → Prop} {xs : list ℕ} :
(filter f xs).length ≤ xs.length :=
begin
sorry,
end
lemma sorted_append {xs ys : list ℕ}
(h₁ : sorted xs)
(h₂ : sorted ys)
(h₃ : ∀ (x ∈ xs) (y ∈ ys), x ≤ y) :
sorted (xs ++ ys) :=
begin
sorry,
end
-- set_option pp.all true
lemma qs_correct {xs xs' : list ℕ}
(h : xs' = quicksort xs) :
sorted xs' ∧ (xs : multiset ℕ) = xs' :=
begin
letI := decidable_pred,
letI := prop_decidable,
letI := nat.decidable_lt, -- comment out this line
subst h,
split,
{ generalize len_def : length xs = len,
induction len using nat.strong_induction_on
with len h₁ generalizing xs,
dsimp at h₁,
cases xs with x xs,
{ simp_rw quicksort },
{ simp_rw quicksort,
apply sorted_append,
sorry,
{ apply h₁,
change length (filter (has_lt.lt x) xs) < len,
simp_rw length at len_def,
subst len_def,
apply lt_succ_of_le,
{ apply filter_length },
{ refl }},
sorry }},
sorry,
sorry,
end
Kyle Miller (Dec 15 2021 at 08:11):
I haven't really looked at the mwe, but tactic#classical is a way to introduce all the classical decidable instances inside a tactic proof. (This doesn't make decidable things classical, though. tactic#convert and tactic#convert_to can be helpful.)
Eric Wieser (Dec 15 2021 at 09:03):
Removing open_locale
classical should make that easier for you, IMO
Apurva Nakade (Dec 16 2021 at 02:34):
This reminds me of a question I have always had but never quite got to asking here: why do we have to specify decidability at all? Is there any interesting math that is beyond decidability? Why isn't decidability just one of the core axioms in mathlib?
Yakov Pechersky (Dec 16 2021 at 04:08):
Decidability is innately linked to computation. Decidability means you have an algorithm that provides the resolution of some proposition. Decidability is a core axiom in mathlib, accessed by the open_locale classical
. But to say that everything is decidable is to say that the halting problem is not a problem. If everything is decidable, then given an arbitrary calculation (represented by a Turing machine), we can know for sure whether it halts or whether it goes on forever. But Turing proved that this is not the case for arbitrary Turing machines.
Another example is decidable equality of real numbers represented as Cauchy sequences. If I give you two possibly infinite lists, where each one represents the Cauchy sequence, and I promise that both converge to some number, but possibly not the same one, can you decide whether the two sequences actually converge to the same number? It's very easy to say that whether these two sequences are different -- just keep checking each pair of terms until you hit a pair that has two different terms in it. That means that you know that the sequences are different in at least one place. However, to prove that the sequences really do converge to the same number, you would have to check an infinite number of pairs of terms. And that's not possible. You could say "OK I'll check until some radius of convergence, and say they're equal to some epsilon difference", which is useful(!) but not true equality.
Apurva Nakade (Dec 16 2021 at 04:21):
Ah, interesting, thanks a lot! So from what I understand, the decidability criterion is here because Lean is not able to check proofs but also do computations and decidability helps keep track of which functions are computable and which aren't. This clarifies things a lot!
Kyle Miller (Dec 16 2021 at 04:21):
@Apurva Nakade Complementing Yakov's explanation:
Decidability also has to do with wanting to make definitions of things computable. There are two sorts of types, Prop
and Type*
. Objects whose type is an inductive type in Type*
all have some algorithm backing them, and you're able to figure out which constructor created the object in finite time (so you're able to match
on them). Objects whose type is in Prop
(propositions) don't have this property.
The decidable
system is a way to match
on specific Prop
s, and one of the main interfaces is if p then ... else ...
. A decidable p
instance is essentially a function you can compute that returns a concrete boolean for whether or not p
is true. That way you can create things in Type*
that depend on the truth of a proposition, which you otherwise can't do.
Even though every Prop
is definitely equal to true
or false
, there's no general algorithm to evaluate which it is (that's the incompleteness theorem), so Lean/mathlib instead has this decidability system.
This is useful for when you write programs in Lean (like tactics) since then you can use Prop
s for conditions. It can also be nice to know mathematically whether a proposition is decidable, since it means you've reduced a problem to rote computation.
Apurva Nakade (Dec 16 2021 at 04:26):
Thanks! I'll look at the uses of decidability in Lean again. I guess we just power through computations in math a lot and worry about decidability or computability as needed as an afterthought. But we really do use it implicitly every single time we do a computation!
Kyle Miller (Dec 16 2021 at 04:32):
Another use for decidable
is that you can use dec_trivial
to automatically prove things that are decidable (though this seems to have been intentionally weakened recently to make it easier to port mathlib to Lean 4).
Mario Carneiro (Dec 16 2021 at 05:26):
not sure what you mean, dec_trivial
still works in lean 4 although it is now spelled by decide
Kyle Miller (Dec 16 2021 at 05:36):
@Mario Carneiro I could be wrong, but doesn't lean#562 make it so that decidability instances depending on well-founded recursion no longer work?
Mario Carneiro (Dec 16 2021 at 05:36):
yes, but they didn't work even before that
Mario Carneiro (Dec 16 2021 at 05:38):
previously it would unfold the WF lemma, which was hit or miss because it only works if the lemma was proved without axioms (and the majority of even simple theorems use at least propext
). After lean#562 lemmas are not unfolded, so these fail reliably instead of working or failing unpredictably
Last updated: Dec 20 2023 at 11:08 UTC