Zulip Chat Archive
Stream: maths
Topic: Surreal numbers
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 16:17):
Hi,
I'm trying to play around with some surreal numbers in Lean and am looking at the TODO's in the library.
The first TODO says to construct a proof of numeric n
which is a term of type pgame n \to Prop
where n : \nat
.
Amazingly, Lean is able to coerce n : \nat
to n : pgame
. I searched the code for a definition of this coercion but only found pgame.has_zero
and pgame.has_one
. How is this coercion happening?
Thanks,
Johan Commelin (Apr 12 2021 at 16:18):
If you have 0
and 1
(which you found), then you only need +
to get the coercion.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 16:20):
Oh, I see, so Lean is automatically defining n.succ : pgame
as n : pgame + 1 : pgame
This is really efficient! Thanks!
Kevin Buzzard (Apr 12 2021 at 21:27):
I think that actually it defines bit0 n : pgame
to be (n : pgame) + (n : pgame)
and bit1 n : pgame
to be (bit0 n : pgame) + (1 : pgame)
which could in theory be different ;-)
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 21:33):
As far as I remember, there isn't a clear proof that pgame.short_add
is properly commutative and associative.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 22:26):
I tried just hacking my way through to see what the definitions look like for some small cases and the definition becomes unrecognizable at n=2
.
import set_theory.surreal
open pgame
theorem numeric_zero' : numeric 0 :=
begin
split,
repeat {simp},
end
theorem numeric_one' : numeric 1 :=
begin
split,
repeat {simp},
apply numeric_zero',
end
theorem numeric_two' : numeric 2 :=
begin
split,
-- goal is unrecognizable
end
theorem numeric_nat (n : ℕ) : numeric n :=
begin
-- don't even know how to start
end
How does one work with this kind of definition? My guess is to first prove things about numeric n
and show that it can be rewritten in a simplified form but I'm having trouble just unfolding the definition of add.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 22:28):
For example, in "math", I believe 2 is simply {1|} (and possibly few other numbers in the left and right sets) but I'm not able to see how numeric 2
reduces to this.
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 22:29):
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 22:30):
I mean src#pgame.numeric_add
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 22:30):
oy
indeed
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 22:31):
-- TODO prove
-- theorem numeric_nat (n : ℕ) : numeric n := sorry
from the source :scared:
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 22:33):
Oh wow! Thank you so much!!
I totally missed this. I'll spend some time trying to understand the proof.
Scott Morrison (Apr 12 2021 at 23:07):
The proof of numeric_nat
follows in just a few lines from numeric_zero
, numeric_one
, and numeric_add
, just by inducting on n
. I'm not sure why it wasn't done previously.
Scott Morrison (Apr 12 2021 at 23:15):
Scott Morrison (Apr 12 2021 at 23:15):
(Spoiler also contains numeric_omega
.)
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 23:26):
Thanks! I thought so too. I had missed this numeric_add
lemma.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 23:27):
Kevin Buzzard said:
I think that actually it defines
bit0 n : pgame
to be(n : pgame) + (n : pgame)
andbit1 n : pgame
to be(bit0 n : pgame) + (1 : pgame)
which could in theory be different ;-)
What does bit0
mean mathematically? It seems to be doubling the number but that can't be right :o
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 23:29):
That's exactly what it's doing
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 23:30):
You can imagine the binary encoding of a number like 13 : 1101. In Lean, it would be:
set_option pp.numerals false
#check 13 -- bit1 (bit0 (bit1 has_one.one)) : ℕ
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 23:30):
which, read from left to right, is exactly 1 0 1 1
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 12 2021 at 23:31):
It's just a more efficient encoding than the unary 13 = 1 + 1 + ... + 1
Apurva Nakade (Apr 12 2021 at 23:35):
Interesting!!
So internally natural numbers are computed using "binary" induction and not "unary" induction. Nice!
Scott Morrison (Apr 12 2021 at 23:42):
(I'll leave my spoiler tag above starred, and perhaps PR it one day, but if you get there first that would be great! :-)
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 13 2021 at 00:02):
Not natural numbers. Anything that is notated by numerical digits
Apurva Nakade (Apr 13 2021 at 14:13):
Just for the record here's one more solution
Spoiler (numeric_nat numeric_omega)
I'll try to get it in the library.
Scott Morrison (Apr 13 2021 at 14:25):
Looks good, PR away. (Indenting inside begin ... end
blocks! :-)
Scott Morrison (Apr 13 2021 at 14:26):
(Also, in spoiler tags, you can put another ```lean
block inside to get formatting.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 13 2021 at 15:10):
Done. I'll also try to clear the other TODO's in the file.
Would it be a good idea to add some lemmas about simplifying surreal numbers coming from natural numbers, like n \equiv {n - 1 | }
? and the "simplicity rule"?
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 13 2021 at 15:15):
Since surreal has instances for has_zero, has_one, and has_add, nats can automatically be cast to surreal
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 13 2021 at 15:16):
You might want to prove commutativity of the addition defined on surreal.
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 13 2021 at 15:16):
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 13 2021 at 15:18):
docs#nat.cast_add is the proof, basically, for the question you asked
Apurva Nakade (Apr 15 2021 at 15:10):
I'm slowly working on proving properties about the addition of surreal numbers.
Is there a nicer way to write the following code:
import set_theory.surreal
namespace surreal
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x :=
begin
rintros ⟨x, ox⟩,
apply quotient.sound,
apply pgame.zero_add_equiv,
end
theorem add_zero : ∀ x : surreal, x + 0 = x :=
begin
rintros ⟨x, ox⟩,
apply quotient.sound,
apply pgame.add_zero_equiv,
end
instance : add_monoid surreal :=
{ add := add,
add_assoc := add_assoc,
zero := 0,
zero_add := zero_add,
add_zero := add_zero }
end surreal
Weirdly I'm not able to merge the two apply
s.
Thanks,
Kevin Buzzard (Apr 15 2021 at 15:12):
First change apply
to refine:
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x :=
begin
rintros ⟨x, ox⟩,
refine quotient.sound _,
refine pgame.zero_add_equiv _,
end
and then it's easy:
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x :=
begin
rintros ⟨x, ox⟩,
exact quotient.sound (pgame.zero_add_equiv _),
end
Apurva Nakade (Apr 15 2021 at 15:14):
Oh I see, I was missing that _
at the end.
Thanks!
Eric Wieser (Apr 15 2021 at 15:22):
You might find that
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x :=
begin
rintros ⟨x, ox⟩,
exact quotient.sound (pgame.zero_add_equiv _),
end
golfs further to
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x
| ⟨x, ox⟩ := quotient.sound (pgame.zero_add_equiv _)
Eric Wieser (Apr 15 2021 at 15:30):
This works too:
section
-- otherwise the elaborator gets in our way
local attribute [elab_with_expected_type] quotient.ind
instance : add_monoid surreal :=
{ add := add,
add_assoc := add_assoc,
zero := 0,
zero_add := quotient.ind $ λ a, quotient.sound $ pgame.zero_add_equiv _,
add_zero := quotient.ind $ λ a, quotient.sound $ pgame.add_zero_equiv _ }
end
Apurva Nakade (Apr 15 2021 at 15:39):
Thanks, I was trying something like λ ⟨x, ox⟩, ...
but that did not work.
I guess Lean is better at pattern matching | ⟨x, ox⟩ := ...
.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 15 2021 at 15:41):
Eric Wieser said:
You might find that
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x := begin rintros ⟨x, ox⟩, exact quotient.sound (pgame.zero_add_equiv _), end
golfs further to
theorem zero_add : ∀ x : surreal, 0 + x = x | ⟨x, ox⟩ := quotient.sound (pgame.zero_add_equiv _)
I just tried this one out and Lean is throwing a type mismatch error for quotient.sound
Apurva Nakade (Apr 15 2021 at 15:42):
I'm guessing it is not able to infer the setoid type.
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 15 2021 at 15:43):
You can try using quot.sound
and quot.ind
instead, which do not try to infer the setoid on their own.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 15 2021 at 15:44):
Interesting! Thanks,
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 16:56):
Here's a construction of ordered_add_comm_group
instance for surreal numbers:
import set_theory.surreal
open pgame
namespace surreal
def neg : surreal → surreal :=
surreal.lift (λ x ox, ⟦⟨-x, pgame.numeric_neg ox⟩⟧) (λ _ _ _ _ a, quotient.sound (pgame.neg_congr a))
instance : ordered_add_comm_group surreal :=
{ add := surreal.add,
add_assoc := surreal.add_assoc,
zero := 0,
zero_add := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩, exact quotient.sound (pgame.zero_add_equiv _) },
add_zero := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩, exact quotient.sound (pgame.add_zero_equiv _) },
neg := surreal.neg,
sub := λ x y, x + surreal.neg y,
sub_eq_add_neg := by try_refl_tac,
add_left_neg := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩, exact quotient.sound pgame.add_left_neg_equiv },
add_comm := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩ ⟨y, oy⟩, exact quotient.sound pgame.add_comm_equiv },
le := surreal.le,
lt := surreal.lt,
le_refl := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩, refl },
le_trans := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩ ⟨y, oy⟩ ⟨z, oz⟩, exact pgame.le_trans },
lt_iff_le_not_le := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩ ⟨y, oy⟩, exact pgame.lt_iff_le_not_le ox oy },
le_antisymm := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩ ⟨y, oy⟩ h₁ h₂, exact quotient.sound ⟨h₁, h₂⟩ },
add_le_add_left := by { rintros ⟨x, ox⟩ ⟨y, oy⟩ hx ⟨z, oz⟩, exact pgame.add_le_add_left hx } }
end surreal
Is there any way I can improve the code?
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 17:05):
The next TODO in the surreal.lean file is the construction of a homomorphism surreal → game
but I don't know what game
is.
So, I'm instead thinking of constructing the "dyadic rationals" as surreal numbers.
Eric Wieser (Apr 19 2021 at 17:13):
There's no point defining sub
there like that, it will use that definition for you automatically.
Eric Wieser (Apr 19 2021 at 17:14):
However, it might be worth doing if you defined it as ⟦⟨x-y, pgame.numeric_sub ox oy⟩⟧
instead
Eric Wieser (Apr 19 2021 at 17:14):
Which is more work, but unfolds more nicely
Eric Wieser (Apr 19 2021 at 17:16):
I'd recommend you make a PR with what you have anyway
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 17:27):
Thanks! Will push this to mathlib soon.
I also didn't like just using the sub
definition from some instance in the library but I couldn't figure out how to get Lean to infer it automatically.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 17:29):
Regarding dyadic rationals, I think a good intermediate step is to define and prove the basic properties of the midpoint
function, which I think is the main driver behind the dyadic rational construction
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 17:30):
(maybe there are conditions on the inputs, I forget the details)
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 17:31):
It's awfully convenient to have x - y = x + -y
be defeq. I wouldn't redefine it unless it expands to something crazy with the default definition
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 19:42):
Mario Carneiro said:
Regarding dyadic rationals, I think a good intermediate step is to define and prove the basic properties of the
midpoint
function, which I think is the main driver behind the dyadic rational construction
Do you have a specific property in mind? I think it is true that . More generally, works when and are adjacent numbers created on the same day.
I can try and figure out what this might look like formally.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 21:15):
Right, that latter property is the one I'm talking about. You have to prove that that number is in fact , for example by proving that
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 21:15):
"created on the same day" also sounds a bit finicky
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 21:16):
Is it possible to say anything interesting about when and are just random surreals?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 21:17):
Also, you said "more generally" but the first statement doesn't follow from the second since 0 is born on day 0
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 21:53):
Oh right, 0 isn't born on the same day!
I'll take a look at Conway and try to work out the exact mathematical statement.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 22:01):
So I believe the correct mathematical statement is this: if are the numbers created by day then the is the midpoint of and . But this fails for arbitrary .
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 22:03):
On shortcut is to just prove that . And define as . This will not require the concept of "days".
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:06):
Do we know that the surreals are a field?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:06):
I'm guessing no, but if not then a lot of shortcuts like that won't work
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:07):
Also, what's the proof sketch? The lean version of the definition is pretty different from the set theory definition
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 22:09):
There is a definition of inverse in the library for pgames: https://github.com/leanprover-community/mathlib/blob/0dfac6ebc9cbb286afb013ccfd7c7478a11ba1e5/src/set_theory/surreal.lean#L106
It might be possible to define the field instance for surreal using this.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:13):
Oh, it's not even proved to be numeric
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:13):
that should be fairly easy
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:14):
I lifted those definitions straight off wikipedia. I don't think they came with proofs attached
Apurva Nakade (Apr 19 2021 at 22:15):
Oh cool, let me try this out first then. Thanks!
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:16):
Looking at those expressions, I think commutativity of addition and the other ring axioms should be "straightforward"
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:24):
I think the correct statement regarding midpoints is that if you have a surreal number such that (let's say they are real numbers, and in the easy case the max/min are attained), then
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:26):
Oh no that's not right, is mentioned on wikipedia
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:39):
Oh, pgame
already has add_comm
proved, it just needs to be packed up
Mario Carneiro (Apr 19 2021 at 22:39):
don't see anything about the other field operations though
Apurva Nakade (Apr 20 2021 at 14:51):
Right, I'll work on proving things about mul
first.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 21 2021 at 23:34):
I spent hours (unsuccessfully) trying to prove x * 0 = 0
for pgame
s by hand only to discover this:
import set_theory.surreal
universes u
namespace pgame
def mul_zero_relabelling :
Π (x : pgame.{u}), relabelling (x * 0) 0
:= by {rintros ⟨⟩, tidy}
end pgame
This is insane! How is tidy
so powerful? Is this a valid proof? It almost feels like I'm cheating somehow.
Alex J. Best (Apr 21 2021 at 23:35):
If you run tidy?
instead, it will tell you what tactics it did.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 21 2021 at 23:38):
This is the suggestion:
fsplit, work_on_goal 0 { dsimp at *, fsplit, work_on_goal 0 { intros ᾰ, cases ᾰ, work_on_goal 0 { cases ᾰ, cases ᾰ_snd }, cases ᾰ, cases ᾰ_snd }, work_on_goal 0 { intros ᾰ, cases ᾰ }, work_on_goal 0 { intros x, cases x, work_on_goal 0 { cases x, cases x_snd }, cases x, cases x_snd }, intros x, cases x }, work_on_goal 0 { dsimp at *, fsplit, work_on_goal 0 { intros ᾰ, cases ᾰ, work_on_goal 0 { cases ᾰ, cases ᾰ_snd }, cases ᾰ, cases ᾰ_snd }, work_on_goal 0 { intros ᾰ, cases ᾰ }, work_on_goal 0 { intros x, cases x, work_on_goal 0 { cases x, cases x_snd }, cases x, cases x_snd }, intros x, cases x }, work_on_goal 0 { intros i, cases i, work_on_goal 0 { cases i, cases i_snd }, cases i, cases i_snd }, intros j, cases j
:dizzy:
Eric Rodriguez (Apr 21 2021 at 23:38):
yeah was just about to post that, lol
Eric Rodriguez (Apr 21 2021 at 23:38):
finish
is also good
Eric Rodriguez (Apr 21 2021 at 23:39):
(although in this case it completely fails)
Apurva Nakade (Apr 21 2021 at 23:42):
tidy
ftw :sunglasses:
Scott Morrison (Apr 22 2021 at 00:24):
Even though that's a fairly large tactic script coming out of tidy
, I would bet it's straightforward to hand-edit down to something much smaller, even before you understand what it is doing. Very often it runs cases
unnecessarily (or "too early"), and this is a large part of why it is slow. Also very often it calls dsimp
unnecessarily.
Scott Morrison (Apr 22 2021 at 00:26):
The first step of mindlessly golfing a tidy
proof is to add newlines and indentation, so you have a hope. :-)
Kevin Buzzard (Apr 22 2021 at 06:28):
It looks to me like for the most part it's taking terms apart, with a bit of simp
thrown in. If it's slow to run you might want to replace with the output of tidy?
and then start aggressively using rintro
and rcases
.
Yeah I've seen both tidy
and nlinarith
do things they should never be able to do
Apurva Nakade (Apr 23 2021 at 15:33):
I did manage to simplify it quite a bit, and in the process discovered rintros?
:
import set_theory.surreal
open pgame
namespace pgame
/-- `x * 0` has exactly the same moves as `0`. -/
theorem mul_zero_relabelling : Π (x : pgame), relabelling (x * 0) 0
| (mk xl xr xL xR) :=
⟨by fsplit; rintro (⟨_, ⟨⟩⟩ | ⟨_, ⟨⟩⟩),
by fsplit; rintro (⟨_, ⟨⟩⟩ | ⟨_, ⟨⟩⟩),
by rintro (⟨_, ⟨⟩⟩ | ⟨_, ⟨⟩⟩),
by rintro ⟨⟩⟩
/-- `0 * x` has exactly the same moves as `0`. -/
theorem zero_mul_relabelling : Π (x : pgame), relabelling (0 * x) 0
| (mk xl xr xL xR) :=
⟨by fsplit; rintro (⟨⟨⟩, _⟩ | ⟨⟨⟩, _⟩),
by fsplit; rintro (⟨⟨⟩, _⟩ | ⟨⟨⟩, _⟩),
by rintro (⟨⟨⟩,_⟩ | ⟨⟨⟩,_⟩),
by rintro ⟨⟩⟩
end pgame
Apurva Nakade (Apr 25 2021 at 16:55):
I'm trying to prove basic properties about the multiplication of surreal numbers.
I have several proofs written out completely but all of the need the following lemmas, which I'm having trouble proving:
import set_theory.surreal
open pgame
def neg_congr_relabelling {x y : pgame}
(h₁ : x.relabelling y) : (-x).relabelling (-y) :=
sorry
def add_congr_relabelling {w x y z : pgame}
(h₁ : w.relabelling x) (h₂ : y.relabelling z) : (w + y).relabelling (x + z) :=
sorry
I can try induction on the various variables but that seems like the wrong way to prove these.
Morally, these should be defined recursively but I'm not accustomed to writing recursion in Lean.
Any suggestions?
Thanks,
Mario Carneiro (Apr 25 2021 at 17:08):
Here's a proof for the first one. The recursion pattern is borrowed from relabelling.symm
def neg_congr_relabelling : ∀ {x y : pgame}, x.relabelling y → (-x).relabelling (-y)
| (mk xl xr xL xR) (mk yl yr yL yR) ⟨L_equiv, R_equiv, L_relabelling, R_relabelling⟩ :=
⟨R_equiv, L_equiv,
λ i, neg_congr_relabelling (by simpa using R_relabelling (R_equiv i)),
λ i, neg_congr_relabelling (by simpa using L_relabelling (L_equiv.symm i))⟩
Apurva Nakade (Apr 26 2021 at 13:52):
Thanks!
I've managed to get a proof for surreal.mul_comm
import set_theory.surreal
open pgame
namespace pgame
/-- An explicit description of the moves for Left in `x * y`. -/
def left_moves_mul {x y : pgame} : (x * y).left_moves
≃ x.left_moves × y.left_moves ⊕ x.right_moves × y.right_moves :=
by { cases x, cases y, refl, }
/-- An explicit description of the moves for Right in `x * y`. -/
def right_moves_mul {x y : pgame} : (x * y).right_moves
≃ x.left_moves × y.right_moves ⊕ x.right_moves × y.left_moves :=
by { cases x, cases y, refl, }
@[simp] lemma mk_mul_move_left_inl {xl xr yl yr} {xL xR yL yR} {i j} :
(mk xl xr xL xR * mk yl yr yL yR).move_left (sum.inl (i,j))
= (mk xl xr xL xR).move_left i * (mk yl yr yL yR)
+ (mk xl xr xL xR) * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_left j
- (mk xl xr xL xR).move_left i * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_left j
:= rfl
@[simp] lemma mul_move_left_inl {x y : pgame} {i j} :
(x * y).move_left ((@left_moves_mul x y).symm (sum.inl (i,j)))
= x.move_left i * y + x * y.move_left j - x.move_left i * y.move_left j
:= by {cases x, cases y, refl}
@[simp] lemma mk_mul_move_left_inr {xl xr yl yr} {xL xR yL yR} {i j} :
(mk xl xr xL xR * mk yl yr yL yR).move_left (sum.inr (i,j))
= (mk xl xr xL xR).move_right i * (mk yl yr yL yR)
+ (mk xl xr xL xR) * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_right j
- (mk xl xr xL xR).move_right i * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_right j
:= rfl
@[simp] lemma mul_move_left_inr {x y : pgame} {i j} :
(x * y).move_left ((@left_moves_mul x y).symm (sum.inr (i,j)))
= x.move_right i * y + x * y.move_right j - x.move_right i * y.move_right j
:= by {cases x, cases y, refl}
@[simp] lemma mk_mul_move_right_inl {xl xr yl yr} {xL xR yL yR} {i j} :
(mk xl xr xL xR * mk yl yr yL yR).move_right (sum.inl (i,j))
= (mk xl xr xL xR).move_left i * (mk yl yr yL yR)
+ (mk xl xr xL xR) * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_right j
- (mk xl xr xL xR).move_left i * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_right j
:= rfl
@[simp] lemma mul_move_right_inl {x y : pgame} {i j} :
(x * y).move_right ((@right_moves_mul x y).symm (sum.inr (i, j)))
= x.move_right i * y + x * y.move_left j - x.move_right i * y.move_left j
:= by {cases x, cases y, refl}
@[simp] lemma mk_mul_move_right_inr {xl xr yl yr} {xL xR yL yR} {i j} :
(mk xl xr xL xR * mk yl yr yL yR).move_right (sum.inr (i,j))
= (mk xl xr xL xR).move_right i * (mk yl yr yL yR)
+ (mk xl xr xL xR) * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_left j
- (mk xl xr xL xR).move_right i * (mk yl yr yL yR).move_left j
:= rfl
@[simp] lemma mul_move_right_inr {x y : pgame} {i j} :
(x * y).move_right ((@right_moves_mul x y).symm (sum.inr (i,j)))
= x.move_right i * y + x * y.move_left j - x.move_right i * y.move_left j
:= by {cases x, cases y, refl}
/-- If `w` has the same moves as `x` and `y` has the same moves as `z`,
then `w + y` has the same moves as `x + z`. -/
def add_congr_relabelling : ∀ {w x y z : pgame},
w.relabelling x → y.relabelling z → (w + y).relabelling (x + z)
| (mk wl wr wL wR) (mk xl xr xL xR) (mk yl yr yL yR) (mk zl zr zL zR)
⟨L_equiv₁, R_equiv₁, L_relabelling₁, R_relabelling₁⟩
⟨L_equiv₂, R_equiv₂, L_relabelling₂, R_relabelling₂⟩ :=
begin
refine ⟨_,_,_,_⟩,
{ fsplit, -- left moves
{ rintro (i|j),
{ exact sum.inl (L_equiv₁ i) },
{ exact sum.inr (L_equiv₂ j) }},
{ rintro (i|j),
{ exact sum.inl (L_equiv₁.symm i) },
{ exact sum.inr (L_equiv₂.symm j) }},
{ rintro (_|_); simp only [equiv.symm_apply_apply] },
{ rintro (_|_); simp only [equiv.apply_symm_apply] }},
{ fsplit, -- right moves
{ rintro (i|j),
{ exact sum.inl (R_equiv₁ i) },
{ exact sum.inr (R_equiv₂ j) }},
{ rintro (i|j),
{ exact sum.inl (R_equiv₁.symm i) },
{ exact sum.inr (R_equiv₂.symm j) }},
{ rintro (_|_); simp only [equiv.symm_apply_apply] },
{ rintro (_|_); simp only [equiv.apply_symm_apply] }},
{ rintro (i|j), -- move left
{ exact add_congr_relabelling
(L_relabelling₁ i)
(⟨L_equiv₂, R_equiv₂, L_relabelling₂, R_relabelling₂⟩) },
{ exact add_congr_relabelling
(⟨L_equiv₁, R_equiv₁, L_relabelling₁, R_relabelling₁⟩)
(L_relabelling₂ j) }},
{ rintro (i|j), -- move right
{ exact add_congr_relabelling
(R_relabelling₁ i)
(⟨L_equiv₂, R_equiv₂, L_relabelling₂, R_relabelling₂⟩) },
{ exact add_congr_relabelling
(⟨L_equiv₁, R_equiv₁, L_relabelling₁, R_relabelling₁⟩)
(R_relabelling₂ j) }},
end
using_well_founded { dec_tac := pgame_wf_tac }
/-- If `x` has the same moves as `y`, then `-x` has the sames moves as `-y`. -/
def neg_congr_relabelling : ∀ {x y : pgame}, x.relabelling y → (-x).relabelling (-y)
| (mk xl xr xL xR) (mk yl yr yL yR) ⟨L_equiv, R_equiv, L_relabelling, R_relabelling⟩ :=
⟨R_equiv, L_equiv,
λ i, neg_congr_relabelling (by simpa using R_relabelling (R_equiv i)),
λ i, neg_congr_relabelling (by simpa using L_relabelling (L_equiv.symm i))⟩
/-- If `w` has the same moves as `x` and `y` has the same moves as `z`,
then `w - y` has the same moves as `x - z`. -/
theorem sub_congr_relabelling {w x y z : pgame}
(h₁ : w.relabelling x) (h₂ : y.relabelling z) : (w - y).relabelling (x - z) :=
add_congr_relabelling h₁ (neg_congr_relabelling h₂)
/-- If `a` has the same moves as `x`, `b` has the same moves as `y`,
and `c` has the same moves as `z`, then `a + b - c` has the same moves as `y + x - z`. -/
lemma add_sub_comm {a b c x y z : pgame}
(h₁ : a.relabelling x) (h₂ : b.relabelling y) (h₃ : c.relabelling z) :
(a + b - c).relabelling (y + x - z) :=
sub_congr_relabelling
(relabelling.trans
(add_comm_relabelling a b)
(add_congr_relabelling h₂ h₁)) h₃
/-- `x * y` has exactly the same moves as `y * x`. -/
theorem mul_comm_relabelling (x y : pgame) : (x * y).relabelling (y * x):=
begin
induction x with xl xr xL xR I1 I2 generalizing y,
induction y with yl yr yL yR J1 J2,
refine ⟨_,_,_,_⟩,
{ fsplit; rintro (⟨i, j⟩ | ⟨i, j⟩);
exact sum.inl (j,i) <|> exact sum.inr (j,i) <|> refl },
{ fsplit; rintro (⟨i, j⟩ | ⟨i, j⟩);
exact sum.inl (j,i) <|> exact sum.inr (j,i) <|> refl },
{ rintro (⟨i, j⟩ | ⟨i, j⟩),
{ exact add_sub_comm (I1 i (mk yl yr yL yR)) (J1 j) (I1 i (yL j)) },
{ exact add_sub_comm (I2 i (mk yl yr yL yR)) (J2 j) (I2 i (yR j)) }},
{ rintro (⟨i, j⟩ | ⟨i, j⟩),
{ exact add_sub_comm (I2 j (mk yl yr yL yR)) (J1 i) (I2 j (yL i)) },
{ exact add_sub_comm (I1 j (mk yl yr yL yR)) (J2 i) (I1 j (yR i)) }}
end
/-- `x * y` is equivalent to `y * x`. -/
theorem mul_comm_equiv (x y : pgame) : (x * y).equiv (y * x) :=
equiv_of_relabelling (mul_comm_relabelling x y)
/-- `x * 0` has exactly the same moves as `0`. -/
theorem mul_zero_relabelling : Π (x : pgame), relabelling (x * 0) 0
| (mk xl xr xL xR) :=
⟨by fsplit; rintro (⟨_,⟨⟩⟩ | ⟨_,⟨⟩⟩),
by fsplit; rintro (⟨_,⟨⟩⟩ | ⟨_,⟨⟩⟩),
by rintro (⟨_,⟨⟩⟩ | ⟨_,⟨⟩⟩),
by rintro ⟨⟩⟩
/-- `x * 0` is equivalent to `0`. -/
theorem mul_zero_equiv (x : pgame) : (x * 0).equiv 0 :=
equiv_of_relabelling (mul_zero_relabelling x)
/-- `0 * x` has exactly the same moves as `0`. -/
theorem zero_mul_relabelling : Π (x : pgame), relabelling (0 * x) 0
| (mk xl xr xL xR) :=
⟨by fsplit; rintro (⟨⟨⟩,_⟩ | ⟨⟨⟩,_⟩),
by fsplit; rintro (⟨⟨⟩,_⟩ | ⟨⟨⟩,_⟩),
by rintro (⟨⟨⟩,_⟩ | ⟨⟨⟩,_⟩),
by rintro ⟨⟩⟩
/-- `0 * x` is equivalent to `0`. -/
theorem zero_mul_equiv (x : pgame) : (0 * x).equiv 0 :=
equiv_of_relabelling (zero_mul_relabelling x)
end pgame
Kevin Buzzard (Apr 26 2021 at 13:56):
That is some very elegant-looking code! I hope you're PR'ing this stuff!
Apurva Nakade (Apr 26 2021 at 14:00):
Thanks! :)
I'll try to optimize the code a bit and PR it away.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 26 2021 at 14:01):
Would you recommend opening up a single PR for the entire thing?
Eric Wieser (Apr 26 2021 at 14:03):
If by "entire thing" you mean that medium-length code block above, definitely
Eric Wieser (Apr 26 2021 at 14:03):
if you mean "Everything you intend to do on surreal numbers after that" too, then probably not!
Eric Wieser (Apr 26 2021 at 14:04):
It's tempting to rename equiv_of_relabelling
to relabelling.equiv
, and then you can probably just remove the zero_mul_equiv
etc lemmas as they become (zero_mul_relabelling x).equiv
Apurva Nakade (Apr 26 2021 at 14:07):
Great, I'll do that.
There are quite a few other _equiv
lemmas in pgame and surreal that are like that. Will need to change that as well.
Eric Wieser (Apr 26 2021 at 14:21):
That might make sense to do as a standalone "chore" or "refactor" PR
Eric Wieser (Apr 26 2021 at 14:21):
If you're looking for an excuse to split your PR in two :)
Apurva Nakade (Apr 26 2021 at 15:11):
It should be fine. Those theorems are never used anywhere :P
Apurva Nakade (Apr 27 2021 at 04:33):
Eric Wieser said:
It's tempting to rename
equiv_of_relabelling
torelabelling.equiv
, and then you can probably just remove thezero_mul_equiv
etc lemmas as they become(zero_mul_relabelling x).equiv
This is turning out to be more complicated than I first thought. I'll follow your suggestion of opening a separate PR for refactoring.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 28 2021 at 18:30):
TIL: For pgames, it turns out that a*(b+c)
is not a relabelling of a*b + a*c
. You get a term x - x
on one side and 0
on the other.
Scott Morrison (Apr 28 2021 at 23:23):
Given multiplication only really works on surreals, not on games, you expect it to break at some point. But it's nice to know this is where it starts, I didn't know that at all!
Eric Wieser (Apr 28 2021 at 23:36):
Is it worth PRing the statement that no such relabeling exists?
Scott Morrison (Apr 28 2021 at 23:44):
Meh, not really.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 00:49):
I too discovered this completely accidentally. Just the number of terms on the two sides do not agree.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 00:49):
My current hope is to define the following:
inductive weak_relabelling : pgame.{u} → pgame.{u} → Type (u+1)
| mk : Π {x y : pgame} (L : x.left_moves ≃ y.left_moves) (R : x.right_moves ≃ y.right_moves),
(∀ (i : x.left_moves), (x.move_left i).equiv (y.move_left (L i))) →
(∀ (j : y.right_moves), (x.move_right (R.symm j)).equiv (y.move_right j)) →
weak_relabelling x y
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 00:50):
and hope that weak_relabelling
implies equiv
.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 00:51):
I think this should provide mul_comm_weak_relabelling
for pgames too, not just surreals.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 29 2021 at 01:54):
Isn't this just the same as equiv
?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 29 2021 at 01:55):
why not prove equiv
directly?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 29 2021 at 01:55):
(specifically, rather than a new inductive that should be a lemma about equiv
)
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 02:45):
For equiv
we'll need to show that a*(b+c) \le a*b + a*c
and a*b + a*c \le a*(b+c)
.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 02:45):
I'm not entirely sure how to do either tbh
Scott Morrison (Apr 29 2021 at 03:55):
Mario is suggesting that you prove
lemma foo {x y : pgame} (L : x.left_moves ≃ y.left_moves) (R : x.right_moves ≃ y.right_moves),
(∀ (i : x.left_moves), (x.move_left i).equiv (y.move_left (L i))) →
(∀ (j : y.right_moves), (x.move_right (R.symm j)).equiv (y.move_right j)),
x.equiv y
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 05:01):
I see, so instead of an inductive type do a lemma. Sounds good!
Mario Carneiro (Apr 29 2021 at 05:02):
By the way, if you are wondering how to prove the lemma, note that this is exactly the inductive step in the proof of equiv_of_relabelling
Apurva Nakade (Apr 29 2021 at 05:05):
Awesome, thanks!!
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 15:45):
Any suggestions for proving this:
import set_theory.pgame
local infix ` ≈ ` := pgame.equiv
lemma aux {a b c d e : pgame} : (a + b) + (c + d) - (e + b) ≈ a + c - e + d :=
sorry
?
This is the last lemma I need for proving left_distrib_equiv
.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 15:46):
do you have the additive group lemmas?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 15:47):
you shouldn't need to resort to relabellings all the time
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 15:59):
I'm having trouble because the equiv
instead of =
.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:00):
There is an instance of add_comm_group
for surreal
but nothing for pgames
.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:00):
If only there were a quotient you could use...
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:00):
Q: why do you care about pgame?
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:01):
Right now mul
is not defined for surreals
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:02):
it respects the quotient, doesn't it?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:02):
also this lemma doesn't use mul
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:03):
Ah, I need this as an intermediate step for proving a * (b + c) = a * b + a * c
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:03):
i meant equiv for pgames
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:03):
I am saying, forget about pgames except as an implementation detail of surreal
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:04):
lift mul to surreal
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:04):
Yeah, there is a missing piece numeric_mul
for descending mul
to surreal
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:04):
I'll try to prove that directly
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:04):
Thanks!
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:05):
There may be a use for the quotient of pgame by equiv, without the numeric part
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:05):
that would be the easiest way to prove the theorem you mention
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:06):
I'm not sure what the benefit of restricting to numeric is, I guess some laws don't hold
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:06):
Ah interesting, I think Conway calls them pseudo-numbers
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:07):
Yeah, I can totally do that and all the proofs will simplify a lot!
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:08):
Would it then make sense to change the definition of surreals
as a subtype of pseudo-numbers
?
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:08):
ah, pgame.star
is a witness to the failure of partial ordering
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:09):
Right, they have the ring structure but not the order or field structures
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:14):
Oops, this already exists
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:14):
that's game
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:21):
Great, I'll check that out and figure out how to connect it back to surreal numbers.
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:22):
Actually there is a complication, because I think that pgame.numeric
does not respect the equivalence relation. You can take as the subtype the assertion that some pgame in the equivalence class is numeric, but then functions that are lifted have to sometimes be evaluated on non-numeric pgames
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:23):
Alternatively, you can just leave the definition as is and construct an injection surreal -> game
so that you can prove theorems about surreal by injecting them into game
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:34):
Creating surreal -> game
is a more natural thing to do. But I still need to define mul
on surreals.
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:35):
I suspect that it should not be too difficult
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:35):
Here is a proof of your lemma using game
import set_theory.game tactic.abel
local infix ` ≈ ` := pgame.equiv
lemma aux {a b c d e : pgame} : (a + b) + (c + d) - (e + b) ≈ a + c - e + d :=
begin
letI := pgame.setoid,
apply @quotient.exact pgame,
change (⟦a⟧ + ⟦b⟧ + (⟦c⟧ + ⟦d⟧) - (⟦e⟧ + ⟦b⟧) : game) = ⟦a⟧ + ⟦c⟧ + -⟦e⟧ + ⟦d⟧,
abel,
end
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:36):
Awesome, thanks so much!
Yakov Pechersky (Apr 30 2021 at 16:38):
No need for letI
, just apply @quotient.exact' pgame
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:39):
actually just deleting the letI is enough
Mario Carneiro (Apr 30 2021 at 16:39):
because this is actually the official setoid on pgame
Apurva Nakade (Apr 30 2021 at 16:42):
This trick of jumping to games
looks really useful. I can probably use it to simplify a lot of other nasty proofs in surreal.lean
.
Apurva Nakade (May 01 2021 at 05:19):
When I added import set_theory.game
to surreal.lean
I started getting type mismatch errors.
For example here : https://github.com/leanprover-community/mathlib/blob/6b6366b351f3e3c242e620aa0c39a4dc1eca8c10/src/set_theory/surreal.lean#L408 (on branch surreal_mul_distrib)
I am getting the following error:
type mismatch at application
has_add.add w
term
w
has type
pgame : Type (u+1)
but is expected to have type
game : Type (?+1)
state:
w x y z : pgame,
ow : w.numeric,
ox : x.numeric,
oy : y.numeric,
oz : z.numeric,
ix : x.left_moves,
hix : w ≤ x.move_left ix,
iz : z.left_moves,
hiz : y ≤ z.move_left iz
⊢ w + y ≤ x.move_left ix + z
Lean is interpreting has_add.add
as the addition of game
s instead of pgame
s.
The \le
also broke in a few places but I was able to fix it using pgame.le_refl
.
Any suggestions on how to resolve this? Thanks,
Mike Shulman (Feb 15 2022 at 16:57):
What is the status of multiplication of surreal numbers in mathlib? In the documentation here I see
The definition of multiplication for surreal numbers is surprisingly difficult and is currently missing in the library...This will make for a fun and challenging project.
but it sounds from the discussion above as though some progress was made? I have a student who might be interested in contributing to this if it is still open.
Rob Lewis (Feb 15 2022 at 18:27):
@Apurva Nakade ?
Apurva Nakade (Feb 15 2022 at 18:37):
Hi @Mike Shulman , I gave up on trying to prove that product of numbers is a number because the proofs got too long and my local machine could not handle them! I don't think anyone is working on this right now. It should make for a nice project but the theorems in Conway's book are not enough and one would need to come up with smart ways to simplify the proof.
Apurva Nakade (Feb 15 2022 at 18:40):
Once you have this, the later proofs would simplify greatly, especially the theorems in docs#surreal.dyadic so it would be amazing if your students can make it work.
Apurva Nakade (Feb 15 2022 at 18:44):
Theorem 3.8 here is the one I tried formalizing.
Mike Shulman (Feb 15 2022 at 18:50):
Thanks!
Michael Stoll (Feb 16 2022 at 20:28):
Hi, as it happens, I was sending an email to Mario Carneiro just today with essentially the same question that @Mike Shulman asked: I also have a student who would be interested in working on this for her Master's thesis.
Since I am responsible for the proof of Theorem 3.8 in the paper linked to by @Apurva Nakade (even though I did this quite some time ago), I would hope that I can provide enough help to my student to get the proof (or a variant of it) formalized.
On the other hand, I would not want to sort of "steal" the topic from @Mike Shulman , who asked before me. So I'm not sure how to proceed from here...
Mike Shulman (Feb 16 2022 at 23:13):
I will PM you.
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:14):
Hi, I'm working on this!
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:15):
I believe to have found a way to complete the proof of multiplication well definedness in a way that is actually nice to work with
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:15):
I'm only like 80% sure that this works
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:17):
The precise statement you prove is this 370964201478553600.png
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:18):
And the way you prove this is by proving that for any game g, if x + y + z is a relabelling of g, then that statement is true
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:18):
You induct on g using the subsequent
relation
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:20):
I'll try actually writing the proof down later today or tomorrow, wish me luck!
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 10:26):
Oh, and this works since you just get the inductive hypothesis with subsequent and reordered arguments, which means that the sum ends up a relabelling of some subsequent game
Violeta Hernández (Apr 24 2022 at 17:43):
Update: the exact induction I posted doesn't work, but I got something pretty similar that seems very promising. I'll be posting my progress on the surreal_mul
branch.
Eric Wieser (Apr 24 2022 at 21:42):
Violeta Hernández (Apr 28 2022 at 17:23):
Great news everyone! I believe I finally nailed the induction hypothesis
Violeta Hernández (Apr 28 2022 at 17:23):
I've updated the branch
Violeta Hernández (Apr 28 2022 at 17:23):
If we prove mul_args.result
, the result follows
Violeta Hernández (Apr 28 2022 at 17:23):
And that itself can be proven by well foundedness on the relation I defined on that type
Violeta Hernández (Apr 28 2022 at 17:23):
I'll continue sketching the proof in the following days
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:55):
I've run into a problem I did not expect to run into
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:55):
I think mathlib
may have the wrong definition of <
on games?
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:57):
ONAG doesn't seem to define <
, but it does define ≰
, which is already really weird, given that in mathlib, x < y
is equivalent to ¬ y ≤ x
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:58):
This other PDF I found does define <
, but it defines x < y
as x ≤ y ∧ ¬ y ≤ x
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:58):
Which is the definition that would hold if <
came from a partial_order
, but mathlib
makes it clear that those two definitions conflict?
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:59):
So, what's the deal here? Was the choice of defining x < y
as ¬ y ≤ x
intentional?
Violeta Hernández (May 03 2022 at 23:59):
Or was it some accident we've perpetrated that has somehow not broken anything yet?
Reid Barton (May 04 2022 at 00:01):
Violeta Hernández said:
given that in mathlib,
x < y
is equivalent to¬ y ≤ x
Are you talking about game
in particular?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:02):
Oh yeah, I should have mentioned that
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:02):
I'm talking about both pgame
and game
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:06):
Yeah, there is something very wrong
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:06):
Every source I've looked says that 0 < G
means that Left can enforce a win in G
no matter who starts
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:06):
And analogously for G < 0
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:07):
This conflicts directly with pgame.star_lt_zero
Reid Barton (May 04 2022 at 00:08):
It looks intentional for sure but I agree it seems strange.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:10):
This seems to go all the way back to https://github.com/leanprover-community/mathlib/commit/b41277c70937d8cd46639bbef674e656e8e397dd
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:11):
@Scott Morrison what's your justification for this?
Reid Barton (May 04 2022 at 00:13):
I would even go so far as to say it is wrong, given that the module docstring says the theory is based on ONAG.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:16):
Yeah, I'm increasingly convinced that this is flat out wrong
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:17):
My theory is this: the easiest way to define ≤
was to define both it and its negation simultaneously via Conway induction, and it was decided that the negation was going to be called <
for convenience
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:18):
I think this predates me: the stuff on pgame
was adapted from existing material on surreal
, and I just followed how that had been done. (I think? I'm very open to the possibility I misremember things, and did things badly wrong. :-)
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:19):
Is the fix just to rename <
on pgame
to ≰
?
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:20):
I'm not sure anything is "wrong", just a terribly misleading symbol is being used. :-)
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:20):
Well, it's not just that
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:20):
If we're going to do that, we're also going to have to rename a bunch of theorems, refactor others, etc.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:20):
And we're also going to have to add the correct API for the correct <
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:20):
By the way, I dug a bit deeper and I found https://github.com/leanprover-community/mathlib/commit/901178e2084d7d4a97bc2ddef68135eb124aa130
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:21):
So it seems like this goes back to @Mario Carneiro
Reid Barton (May 04 2022 at 00:22):
I guess the definition of <
was generalized from surreal
(where it is correct) to game
(where it is not)
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:22):
I don't understand though when you say "it's not just that", however: isn't the only problem that we should have used a different symbol than <
? After replacing the symbols and appropriately updating declaration names, there's no discrepancy from ONAG, right?
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:23):
And nothing currently in pgame.lean
has anything to say about "the real <
" used in other references?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:24):
What I mean is, even if there's not really any maths to fix (Lean won't let us prove false things, that's kind of the point), there's a lot of API that needs to be tweaked
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:25):
(Sorry, above I suggested we just need to replace all the use of <
with ≰
, but that's obviously literally wrong, because the order of arguments needs to flip.)
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 00:25):
But yes, I agree this is worth fixing.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:26):
I'll get to this in a few hours
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 00:29):
Ah! So game
really ought to be a preorder
, just as literally anything else in the library. I was really confused so as to why <
on games ought to escape the rule.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 00:59):
In fact, a partial_order
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 01:00):
And what's more, an ordered_add_comm_group
Junyan Xu (May 04 2022 at 02:35):
image.png
image.png
Here are the notations from Winning Ways (p.29, p.32, 2nd edition)
The same notations are on ONAG (1976), p.73, p.78:
image.png
Junyan Xu (May 04 2022 at 02:38):
So < should be ⧏ (⧏
)
Vertical bar beside right triangle: ⧐
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x29d0
Left triangle beside vertical bar: ⧏
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x29cf
In block: Miscellaneous Mathematical Symbols-B
Junyan Xu (May 04 2022 at 03:01):
Violeta Hernández said:
In fact, a
partial_order
Didn't you just claim game
isn't a partial_order
? (I think it is.)
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 08:51):
Precisely. Currently game
is not a partial order when you use docs#game.has_lt. The question is whether we should make docs#game.partial_order an instance and use the <
from there.
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 10:48):
I had raised precisely this point (that <
on games in mathlib is not compatible with <
as defined by Conway &Co) in private communication with @Mario Carneiro a while ago. I'd be strongly in favor of changing the mathlib definition to be compatible with the literature.
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 10:50):
The notation is used on wikipedia; I believe this is where I got it from
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 10:50):
not on games, on surreals
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 10:50):
BTW, it was mostly me who developed the proof of Theorem 3.8 in Schleicher-Stoll (trying to make Conway's somewhat vague arguments precise).
It is nice to see that this proof apparently can be formalized (and simplified in the process)!
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 10:53):
Mario Carneiro said:
not on games, on surreals
This is the point: On surreals, <
and <|
are the same, since numbers are never fuzzy to each other.
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 10:53):
But for games, there is the possibility that two games are incomparable ("fuzzy").
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 10:55):
I believe that the definition currently called <
is important and plays a central role in the theory, but it is not obvious to me that this relation corresponds to <
or <|
and it would be good to have some literature evidence of such
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 11:03):
By docs#game.not_le, for games, the current definition implies that x < y
is the same as ¬y ≤ x
.
However (as was pointed out in this thread above), ONAG defines x <| y
as ¬y ≤ x
(on page 78) and x < y
as x ≤ y ∧ ¬y ≤ x
. (BTW, Conway defines <
the same way for (surreal) numbers (on page 4), but it eventually turns out that ≤
defines a linear order on numbers.)
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 11:05):
Oooh, this is why the literature on games was so confusing to me. I never realized that x <| y
just meant ¬ y ≤ x
.
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 11:06):
(One motivation for Dierk Schleicher and myself to write our paper was that we felt that the order (first numbers, then games) in ONAG has the logic backwards, beacuse numbers are really special games...)
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 11:06):
Should we even define <|
? game
is a partial order among many others and I can't justify the fact that it gets to have a symbol that would make sense everywhere else but isn't used.
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:07):
The mutually recursive definition of <|
and <=
gives them equal status, even though they are provably negations of each other
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:08):
I think that is an argument that they should exist as definitions; for the notation I don't have much of an opinion
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 11:09):
It may make sense to also define ||
, to have all four possibilities and their combinations...
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 11:10):
Sure, but do we want to use <|
after bootstrapping ≤
? is your argument that we should do this because (≤)ᶜ
doesn't have the recursive properties of <|
? (but do we use those recursive properties anywhere?)
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:10):
note that <|
is actually taken IIRC for some silly definition on option that is never used
Johan Commelin (May 04 2022 at 11:11):
But there is
Junyan Xu said:
So < should be ⧏ (
⧏
)
Vertical bar beside right triangle: ⧐
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x29d0
Left triangle beside vertical bar: ⧏
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x29cf
In block: Miscellaneous Mathematical Symbols-B
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:11):
https://github.com/leanprover-community/lean/blob/f722a688012753f6adbd57e3df7499d498d82945/library/init/data/option/basic.lean#L42-L43 <-- someone should PR remove these
Johan Commelin (May 04 2022 at 11:13):
Never used in mathlib, afaict
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:14):
I saw someone use lhoare
once but it's just get_or_else
with reversed argument order
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:15):
In any case I think these surreal/game notations would be localized so the option definitions don't matter
Eric Wieser (May 04 2022 at 11:18):
What does lhoare
stand for?
Eric Wieser (May 04 2022 at 11:20):
Could also use ≰
(not less than or equal, U+2270, ≰) as notation, although my font makes a meal of it
Johan Commelin (May 04 2022 at 11:21):
Presumably "left/right operator" in Hoare logic or something like that (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hoare_logic)
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 11:25):
Yaël Dillies said:
Sure, but do we want to use
<|
after bootstrapping≤
? is your argument that we should do this because(≤)ᶜ
doesn't have the recursive properties of<|
? (but do we use those recursive properties anywhere?)
⧏
(and ⧐
) are used in various statements and proofs in ONAG, so they would be useful to have if we want to stay close to the standard reference.
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 11:27):
If we end up really using this as a separate definition/symbol, it should
- be available from
has_le
, instead of being specialized togame
- have a suggestive notation, to make it clear that it's just the negation of
≤
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 11:27):
After all, we do have docs#ne as a separate definition with notation ≠
.
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 11:28):
It seems to me that the main argument for having a separate definition instead of just separate notation is that it allows dot notation.
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:39):
Eric Wieser said:
What does
lhoare
stand for?
like Johan I believe the names come from "left/right + [Tony] Hoare", but these are not operators I recognize from hoare logic
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 11:41):
unfortunately the originating commit doesn't give any clue as to the origin or intent behind the definitions
Kevin Buzzard (May 04 2022 at 12:43):
Mario Carneiro said:
https://github.com/leanprover-community/lean/blob/f722a688012753f6adbd57e3df7499d498d82945/library/init/data/option/basic.lean#L42-L43 <-- someone should PR remove these
You CS people can have them, we want fancy unicode for games, not ASCII art.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 14:44):
@Michael Stoll the simplification I had found relied on a property that was true for mathlib <
but not actually correct for the true <
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 14:45):
So other than restate depth in terms of birthdays and merge P2 with P4, it's almost the same argument
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 14:46):
I personally prefer the not less or equal symbol here, I find it much more straightforward (and I believe this is what Conway uses in ONAG)
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 14:47):
That said I'm not convinced that it's worth having as a separate relation, rather than just writing down \neg x \le y
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 14:59):
I also agree with Yaël that if we're going to make it a separate relation, it shouldn't be localized to games
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 14:59):
I imagine many of the theorems for \notle in games are still true on preorders
Michael Stoll (May 04 2022 at 15:00):
Violeta Hernández said:
So other than restate depth in terms of birthdays and merge P2 with P4, it's almost the same argument
OK, thanks for the clarification. The main thing is that the proof is correct (which I have to admit I was only 99% certain about).
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:52):
I wonder how useful it is to have these lemmas on ¬ x ≤ y
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:52):
@[simp] theorem mk_le_mk {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
(⟨xl, xr, xL, xR⟩ : pgame) ≤ ⟨yl, yr, yL, yR⟩ ↔
(∀ i, ¬ mk yl yr yL yR ≤ xL i) ∧
(∀ j, ¬ yR j ≤ mk xl xr xL xR) :=
sorry
@[simp] theorem mk_not_le_mk {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
¬ mk yl yr yL yR ≤ mk xl xr xL xR ↔
(∃ i, mk xl xr xL xR ≤ yL i) ∨
(∃ j, xR j ≤ mk yl yr yL yR) :=
sorry
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:52):
They were previously lemmas on <
which made sense to have, but now?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:53):
those kind of lemmas will not play as well with simp
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:53):
Hmm, you're right
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:53):
I'm wondering if we should have the former at all
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:54):
?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:54):
*latter
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:54):
Those are the definition of <=
and <|
, of course we want them
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:54):
and they make good simp lemmas too
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:55):
That's only assuming that we actually have notation for <|
, and I'm skeptical of this being a good idea
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:55):
if there was no such notation it would still be exactly as written, just without the notation
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:56):
True, but surely it would be easier to just use mk_le_mk
and, if needed, push_neg
?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:58):
What's more, this isn't even the form that push_neg
gives for the lemma
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 17:58):
@[simp] theorem mk_not_le_mk {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
¬ mk yl yr yL yR ≤ mk xl xr xL xR ↔
(∀ i, ¬ mk xl xr xL xR ≤ yL i) →
(∃ j, xR j ≤ mk yl yr yL yR) :=
by { rw mk_le_mk, push_neg, refl }
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:58):
That's not a good form at all
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 17:59):
I'm not a fan of gratuitous push_neg. These kind of theorems don't really need LEM and the proofs are shorter that way too
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:00):
I know most people don't care but I occasionally clean up LEM usage in fundamental logic lemmas where possible
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:01):
The negations here just confuse the tactics by making one variation look "more complex" than the other, leading to lots of symmetry breaking
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:01):
That might be a case for actually having a \notle
relation on games
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:03):
I have a slight preference for x <| y
over y \notle x
because it puts the variables in the right order
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:03):
...in fact I think it has to be in that order for the recursive definition to work
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:04):
because (x <| y, x <= y)
is what is defined by recursion
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:04):
Right
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:05):
Still, what kind of annoys me is that we'd be dealing with a really basic relation and have almost no API for it
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:05):
why no API?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:06):
I mean, that thing I mentioned earlier, that most of the basic results on <|
should in fact be basic results of \notle
on preorders
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:06):
I'm not quite sure how we could leverage this
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:07):
We don't have a typeclass for converse-le-preorders so I wouldn't worry about it
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:08):
Also, another question
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:08):
How should the lemmas about <|
be called?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:08):
lf
= less-fuzzy?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:09):
I like that
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:12):
...no, I don't know, I still kinda agree with Yaël that it's silly to define this new symbol for games and nothing else, despite it making sense on any preorder
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:13):
Sure, that's a potential refactor to consider once there is more than 1 example
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:14):
it would be quite a lot of work and lf
would not be nearly as good a name
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:14):
Mario Carneiro said:
The mutually recursive definition of
<|
and<=
gives them equal status, even though they are provably negations of each other
I don't agree with this. I think that our simultaneous definition of these symbols is more of an inductive hack. If we really wanted to, we could have defined ≤
using the standard ZFC definition and just prove that the relation on pairs where entries can be swapped as long as at least one entry decreases is well-founded
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:14):
It's just easier not to do that
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:15):
I disagree, I would say that x <| y
and ~(y <= x)
are not intensionally equal in the same way that a + b
and b + a
are not intensionally equal
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:16):
it is a theorem, proven by induction, that they coincide
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:17):
The refactor I am talking about for preorder
would be to add another field notle
and a proof x \notle y <-> ~(x <= y)
, to be able to change the defeq of the notle
relation beyond the default one
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:18):
Why would it need to be a field of preorder
? We don't do this for \ge
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:18):
because it is changing the defeq
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:19):
This would be pretty easy to circumvent though
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:19):
We could do it for ge
as well, if we had more than 0 examples where we want the defeqs to differ
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:20):
def le_not_ge : Π (x y : pgame), Prop × Prop
| (mk xl xr xL xR) (mk yl yr yL yR) :=
-- the orderings of the clauses here are carefully chosen so that
-- and.left/or.inl refer to moves by Left, and
-- and.right/or.inr refer to moves by Right.
((∀ i : xl, (le_not_ge (xL i) ⟨yl, yr, yL, yR⟩).2) ∧
(∀ j : yr, (le_not_ge ⟨xl, xr, xL, xR⟩ (yR j)).2),
(∃ i : yl, (le_not_ge ⟨xl, xr, xL, xR⟩ (yL i)).1) ∨
(∃ j : xr, (le_not_ge (xR j) ⟨yl, yr, yL, yR⟩).1))
using_well_founded { dec_tac := pgame_wf_tac }
instance : has_le pgame := ⟨λ x y, (le_not_ge x y).1⟩
instance : has_lt pgame := ⟨λ x y, x ≤ y ∧ ¬ y ≤ x⟩
-- We need a few auxiliary theorems before proving that `(le_not_ge x y).2 ↔ ¬ y ≤ x`.
private theorem mk_le_mk_aux {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
mk xl xr xL xR ≤ mk yl yr yL yR ↔
(∀ i, (le_not_ge (xL i) (mk yl yr yL yR)).2) ∧
(∀ j, (le_not_ge (mk xl xr xL xR) (yR j)).2) :=
show (le_not_ge _ _).1 ↔ _, by rw le_not_ge
private theorem mk_not_le_mk_aux {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
(le_not_ge (mk xl xr xL xR) (mk yl yr yL yR)).2 ↔
(∃ i, mk xl xr xL xR ≤ yL i) ∨
(∃ j, xR j ≤ mk yl yr yL yR) :=
show (le_not_ge _ _).2 ↔ _, by { rw le_not_ge, refl }
private theorem le_not_ge_iff_aux {x y : pgame} :
(x ≤ y ↔ ¬ (le_not_ge y x).2) ∧ ((le_not_ge x y).2 ↔ ¬ y ≤ x) :=
begin
induction x with xl xr xL xR IHxl IHxr generalizing y,
induction y with yl yr yL yR IHyl IHyr,
simp only [mk_le_mk_aux, mk_not_le_mk_aux,
not_and_distrib, not_or_distrib, not_forall, not_exists,
and_comm, or_comm, IHxl, IHxr, IHyl, IHyr, iff_self, and_self]
end
private theorem le_not_ge_iff {x y : pgame} : (le_not_ge x y).2 ↔ ¬ y ≤ x :=
le_not_ge_iff_aux.2
@[simp] theorem mk_le_mk {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
mk xl xr xL xR ≤ mk yl yr yL yR ↔
(∀ i, ¬ mk yl yr yL yR ≤ xL i) ∧
(∀ j, ¬ yR j ≤ mk xl xr xL xR) :=
by simp_rw [mk_le_mk_aux, le_not_ge_iff]
theorem mk_not_le_mk {xl xr xL xR yl yr yL yR} :
¬ mk yl yr yL yR ≤ mk xl xr xL xR ↔
(∃ i, mk xl xr xL xR ≤ yL i) ∨
(∃ j, xR j ≤ ⟨yl, yr, yL, yR⟩) :=
by rw [←le_not_ge_iff, mk_not_le_mk_aux]
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:20):
Once you have those last two theorems, there's not really a need to invoke le_not_ge
ever again
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:21):
So I don't think it's worth adding a new field to preorder
for this
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:21):
I don't either
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:21):
I think that pgame
specifically should have a notle definition
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:22):
Hmm... I think I'll take your compromise
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:22):
If there's ever another instance where we want this separate \notle
definition, then we can take whatever theorems about it we prove here, and generalize those to preorders
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:23):
Until then, I'll just make it a definition on pgame
specifically
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:23):
using the le_not_ge_iff
lemma you can pretty easily eliminate <|
in any theorem statements if you don't want to see it
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:23):
Oh and one last thing, what symbol are we going to use then?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:24):
and pretty much the only theorems of interest for these converse-le-preorders are cyclic permutations of le_trans
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:24):
We could use <|
or ⧏
or ◁
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:25):
I think Kevin wants to veto <|
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:26):
I'm not a fan either
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:26):
If we want to stick as closely as possible to Conway, we should be using ⧏
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:26):
(it looks kinda cramped in my font, though)
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:26):
lgtm
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:26):
it lines up in my lean font, it's a bit short on zulip
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:27):
Alright then
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:27):
I'll get refactoring
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:27):
If we're just going to change <
to ⧏
, then not that many things should be different by the end of this
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:28):
Oh, one last thing!
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:28):
The <
error seems to have propagated to one other file
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:28):
winner.lean
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:28):
what error?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:29):
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:29):
These two should just be 0 < G
and G < 0
respectively
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:29):
And to me it seems like it isn't worth having a separate definition for that?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:29):
The new definition of lt
is this already, right?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:30):
x < y <-> x <| y /\ x <= y
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:30):
if so I agree this doesn't need separate definition, we don't have pos
on preorders
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:31):
Alright then
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:31):
For the moment I'll just replace <
with ⧏
in those files, but I'll probably refactor those afterwards
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:32):
it might be worth stuffing the documentation about "left wins" and "right wins" in terms of positive and negative somewhere though, that's not very obvious
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:33):
Ah, this is a more technical issue, but how do you define a new symbol in Lean?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:33):
I tried
local infix ` ⧏ ` := λ x y, (le_lf x y).2
and it tells me something about a missing precedence
command
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:34):
put a :50
or something after the backticks
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:34):
it should probably line up with the numbers from #print <
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:35):
There goes, thanks!
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:39):
Should I also introduce ⧐
with a simp
lemma x ⧐ y ↔ y ⧏ x
or is that not worth it?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 18:43):
let's do our best to pretend gt
doesn't exist
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:43):
Yeah, I don't think it's worth it either
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 18:47):
Just to be sure,
@[simp] theorem not_le {x y : pgame} : ¬ x ≤ y ↔ y ⧏ x := not_le_lf.1
@[simp] theorem not_lf {x y : pgame} : ¬ x ⧏ y ↔ y ≤ x := not_le_lf.2
both of these should be simp
, right?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 19:27):
https://leanprover-community.github.io/mathlib_docs/set_theory/game/pgame.html#pgame.right_response
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 19:27):
Do we really need this? Seems pretty useless to me
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 19:28):
I guess it's a way to prove that x ≤ 0 actually means that Right wins as the second player?
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 19:56):
I don't see any obvious way to do so, it's more or less true by definition
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:04):
Yeah, that's my thought too
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:37):
There's currently a covariant_class_swap_add_lt
instance on pgame
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:37):
Would it be worth it changing it into a covariant_class_swap_add_lf
instance? I don't know if there's any API for covariant relations other than <
or ≤
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 21:37):
No there is not.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:44):
Could that API exist in the future, though? Surely it would just be a matter of not enforcing has_lt
or has_le
in those theorems
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:54):
In fact, I'll in some form need the covariantness of \lf
to prove that of <
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:54):
Since <
is equivalent to \le
and \lf
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 21:55):
Maybe it could be a theorem instead of an instance for now?
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 21:56):
Yes, there's no point in making an instance to use it exactly once.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 22:06):
I mean, it would be nice to have auto-generated add_lf_add
and all those other lemmas, but I guess I can prove them myself for now
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 22:47):
Question
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 22:47):
How can I use ⧏
for both pgame
and game
?
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 22:47):
Having a local infix
is only letting me define it once
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 22:49):
Are you sure? You can overload notation.
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 22:49):
not local notation
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 22:49):
I would just not import the notation or use a subscript
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:03):
I feel like this whole file should just go
https://leanprover-community.github.io/mathlib_docs/set_theory/game/winner.html
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:03):
The main definitions are literally just <
, >
, ||
, and ≈
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:03):
We really do not need new names for these relations
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:07):
I know that it's very bad practice to do more than one big thing in a PR, but if I could just delete that file right now, it would make my lt
refactor a smidge easier
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 23:07):
I have no attachment to it. Presumably it is still a leaf node? We may want to have a meta discussion, separated from this subject matter, about removing old leaf nodes.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:07):
A single other file depends on it
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:08):
nim.lean
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 23:08):
Sorry. I think for this refactor you've got to bring it along.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:08):
:(
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 23:08):
Or propose it first.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:08):
It doesn't make sense to kill it without the refactor
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:08):
Violeta Hernández said:
The main definitions are literally just
<
,>
,||
, and≈
This is only true with the correct definitions of <
and >
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 23:09):
for this PR it should not be hard to replace them with left_wins G := 0 < G
etc and give one line proofs of all the theorems. This will make the deletion an easy sell
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 23:09):
Oh, I see. Okay, let's nuke it.
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 23:10):
in particular, if they aren't one line proofs then you might be missing an API theorem
Scott Morrison (May 04 2022 at 23:10):
Although mario's suggestion is probably even better. :-)
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:10):
I am currently missing the ||
relation
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:11):
I don't know if I should define it now that I defined ⧏
, or if that should come in a subsequent PR
Mario Carneiro (May 04 2022 at 23:11):
I think it makes sense to add, if only to have a place to hang all these winner/loser docs
Yaël Dillies (May 04 2022 at 23:19):
Yeah Fox won't be mad if you remove this file. The point was Sprague-Grundy. If you can keep Spraguuuuuuuue-Grundy compiling, cool.
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:58):
As a matter of fact, I got the entire file to one line proofs
Violeta Hernández (May 04 2022 at 23:58):
Often more like 20 character proofs, haha
Junyan Xu (May 05 2022 at 00:04):
Parallel to: ∥
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x2225
In block: Mathematical Operators
Double vertical line: ‖
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x2016
In block: General Punctuation
Musical symbol double barline: 𝄁
Unicode hexadecimal: 0x1d101
In block: Musical Symbols
The second looks best on my machine in VSCode. (I'm using https://shapecatcher.com/)
wow the first is slanted on my phone but vertical on laptop!
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 01:46):
I feel like the first one might be the one we want? It's the mathematical operator after all
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 01:58):
the first one is used in mathlib already, for vector norm
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 01:59):
...and the second one means fintype cardinality apparently
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 02:00):
probably it's fine to reuse the symbol
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 02:01):
actually you should not reuse the vector norm symbol, it's not localized (it's a notation typeclass)
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 02:02):
what about a symbol like )( ?
Junyan Xu (May 05 2022 at 02:11):
I don't think the second one (‖) is declared as a notation? Here indeed it's used to refer to cardinality, but that's definitely not standard.
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 02:14):
it's declared as a local notation in several files
Mario Carneiro (May 05 2022 at 02:14):
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 02:27):
https://github.com/leanprover-community/mathlib/pull/13963
Scott Morrison (May 05 2022 at 04:45):
I've got to say, I don't like the characterisation that we've had the incorrect definition. We've had a perfectly correct definition for a notion that usually has different notation. (And worse, that in some references the notation we used meant something else, although this was not the case for the cited reference.)
I absolutely agree it warrants fixing, but 1) I'm a bit annoyed as I feel like I'm being told my work on pgame
was "wrong" (I agree the way I did things was ... not great), and 2) people may decide to misleadingly point at this as an example of a formalised library getting a definition wrong, and both of those are easily avoidable, I hope.
Damiano Testa (May 05 2022 at 05:00):
In support of Scott's comment, as an outsider to the topic, I was puzzled at the beginning about what it meant that a definition was "wrong". It took me a while to realize that it meant that it did not align with some other arbitrary choice of definition whose notation looked the same.
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 05:05):
I'd say it's worse than that, I couldn't find any source with the previous definition
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 05:05):
Though perhaps it might be better to say, we used one symbol when we should have used another
Scott Morrison (May 05 2022 at 05:06):
What do you mean? The previous definition is exactly ⧏
, but with the symbol <
instead of ⧏
.
Scott Morrison (May 05 2022 at 05:06):
e.g. it exactly matches the definition in ONAG, using the symbol <
for his ≰
.
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 05:15):
Yeah, that
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 05:16):
We used the wrong symbol, and thought we were deducing results about one symbol when in reality we were deducing results about the other
Scott Morrison (May 05 2022 at 05:20):
(Sorry, maybe I'm just having a bad day. :-) I'm very glad this is fixed now: certainly your PR is a massive improvement and I'm embarrassed to have not understood this myself earlier.)
Kevin Buzzard (May 05 2022 at 06:51):
Re notation: the reason I'm anti <|
is that specifically within the mathematician community people have said to me how much easier lean code is to read than code in other provers, and this seems like a perfect place to reinforce this: "oh look they use exactly the same symbol as in the literature".
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 13:54):
Oh don't worry, I didn't understand this either until I spoke with someone that did know about this and they kept telling me how I was wrong about my inequalities
Violeta Hernández (May 05 2022 at 13:54):
I've learned a lot about games with this refactor
Junyan Xu (Jun 04 2022 at 08:25):
@Michael Stoll @Violeta Hernández
Good news! Surreals now form a linear_ordered_comm_ring
without sorry
!
Violeta Hernández (Jun 04 2022 at 08:25):
Woooo!
Violeta Hernández (Jun 04 2022 at 08:26):
I'm unfortunately spread thin by finals at the moment, so I don't know when I'll have time to review this thoroughly. Might be until Wednesday...
Junyan Xu (Jun 04 2022 at 17:54):
I'm puzzled by the module docstring saying "the surreals form a complete ordered field". I don't think they form a docs#conditionally_complete_linear_order, because for any increasing sequence with an upper bound, the surreal number with the sequence as left options and the upper bound as the unique right option is still an upper bound but smaller than the given upper bound, so there's no least upper bound. Git traces back to #1274 by @Scott Morrison.
Eric Rodriguez (Jun 04 2022 at 18:16):
All complete ordered fields are isomorphic to R, no?
Damiano Testa (Jun 04 2022 at 18:44):
Archimedean?
Yaël Dillies (Jun 04 2022 at 18:51):
Yaël Dillies (Jun 04 2022 at 18:51):
(I'm working on it, the head PR is currently #14307)
Eric Rodriguez (Jun 04 2022 at 19:03):
It doesn't seem to require it from the sources I see, I guess completeness implies archimedean
Eric Rodriguez (Jun 04 2022 at 19:03):
(with order, ofc, else p-adics are a counterexample)
Patrick Stevens (Jun 04 2022 at 19:14):
Yes - see https://mathoverflow.net/questions/362991/who-first-characterized-the-real-numbers-as-the-unique-complete-ordered-field; to paraphrase, if not Archimedean then the set of naturals is bounded above so has a least upper bound; but any upper bound of the natural numbers is not a least upper bound because you can subtract 1 from it.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 04 2022 at 19:41):
I think there's the possibility that this is a complete ordered field on a technicality, just like the ordinals are a lattice on a technicality
Violeta Hernández (Jun 04 2022 at 19:41):
i.e. every small (read ZFC) set of surreals has an infimum and supremum
Violeta Hernández (Jun 04 2022 at 19:41):
Even then, unless I misunderstand something, that docstring shouldn't be there
Damiano Testa (Jun 04 2022 at 20:02):
Ah yes, Archimedean is implied by the rest of the hypotheses: thanks for the link!
Kevin Buzzard (Jun 04 2022 at 21:21):
The surreals are most certainly not archimedean. The confusion is imprecision in the language -- "complete" can mean more than one thing. Wikipedia says something about the issue.
Stuart Presnell (Jun 04 2022 at 21:34):
As discussed here: https://leanprover-community.github.io/archive/stream/116395-maths/topic/reals.20are.20unique.20complete.20ordered.20field.html#131161921
Patrick Stevens (Jun 04 2022 at 22:57):
As a tenuously-related aside which I'm only making because I can never resist the opportunity to plug this paper, Real Analysis In Reverse (https://arxiv.org/pdf/1204.4483.pdf) uses the surreals (or more precisely those with birthday less than $\omega_1$) to prove that "nested bounded closed intervals have nonempty intersection" does not imply "Dedekind complete" in the presence of the other ordered field axioms. It also warns that "It’s easy for students to appeal to the Archimedean Property without realizing they are doing so, especially because concrete examples of non-Archimedean ordered fields are unfamiliar to them."
Mario Carneiro (Jun 05 2022 at 03:31):
Violeta Hernández said:
I think there's the possibility that this is a complete ordered field on a technicality, just like the ordinals are a lattice on a technicality
Surreals are not a complete ordered field on a technicality, namely that they aren't a set and a field is a set
Mario Carneiro (Jun 05 2022 at 03:33):
If you are in a setting (like lean) where the totality of surreals can be discussed, then they are a field but not they are still not complete because there are (proper) subclasses of the surreals which have no supremum
Mario Carneiro (Jun 05 2022 at 03:34):
it is only if you allow the field itself to be proper but not the subsets considered in the definition of Inf
that they appear "complete"
Mario Carneiro (Jun 05 2022 at 03:36):
Similarly, the ordinals are a lattice but not a complete lattice unless you bastardize the definition in some way
Junyan Xu (Jun 05 2022 at 03:39):
it is only if you allow the field itself to be proper but not the subsets considered in the definition of Inf that they appear "complete"
ordinal
and cardinal
are (large) complete linear orders in this sense; the instances docs#ordinal.conditionally_complete_linear_order_bot and docs#cardinal.conditionally_complete_linear_order_bot say that any (possibly large) subsets with an upper bound has a least upper bound, and separately we know that any small subset has an upper bound.
In surreals, any small subset still has an upper bound (just take all elements of the subset as left options), but my argument above shows it has a least upper bound iff it has a maximal element, so surreals aren't even a docs#conditionally_complete_linear_order.
Junyan Xu (Jun 05 2022 at 03:42):
This conditional completeness looks the same as Dedekind completeness in Wikipedia.
Junyan Xu (Jun 05 2022 at 03:43):
I am undetermined whether surreals still can be complete in the uniform space sense (it hasn't become my second nature to unpack definitions via filters), but I feel it's not (even without uniqueness, as in the mathlib definition docs#complete_space).
Violeta Hernández (Jun 05 2022 at 03:46):
A good example of a set without a supremum in surreals is the naturals
Violeta Hernández (Jun 05 2022 at 03:46):
If x is an upper bound, so is x - 1
Junyan Xu (Jun 05 2022 at 03:51):
Yeah, and my argument gives {0,1,2, ... | x} is also an upper bound: it's a surreal because all left options are smaller than the unique right option x, because 0,1,2,... is strictly increasing, so an upper bound must be a strict upper bound (with < instead of ≤; same holds for any subset without maximal element). And any surreal is greater than all its left options, so it's an upper bound. Any surreal is less than all its right options, so it's smaller than x.
Junyan Xu (Jun 05 2022 at 03:52):
{0,1,2, ... | x} might be exactly equal to x - 1 ... No, not necessarily.
Damiano Testa (Jun 05 2022 at 05:56):
This discussion has clarified a lot of uneasiness that I always had about which common assumptions characterise the reals up to order isomorphism! I'm also happy that Archimedean plays a role in this and that "complete" also has several meanings!
Kevin Buzzard (Jun 05 2022 at 09:09):
An example "one level down" of the size issue which Mario was flagging would be that if you only believed in finite sets, but could imagine the rationals existed as some kind of "class" (each element in it can be described using finite sets, and you don't attempt to describe all the elements of Q at once in your language but use predicates instead) then Q is "complete" for you because every nonempty subset of Q is finite in your world and hence has a least upper bound.
Junyan Xu (Jun 05 2022 at 18:26):
It seems well-known that the surreals contain gaps, so morally they shouldn't be complete in any sense, and indeed it's also not complete as a uniform space (Cauchy completeness, with uniform structure from the topological group structure with the order topology). This is stated in the abstract of https://arxiv.org/abs/1307.7392v3, and p.18 onwards shows any Cauchy sequence indexed by the class of all ordinals either converge to a surreal or to a Type Ia gap. The mathlib definition docs#complete_space requires that every Cauchy filter converges to some surreal, which is equivalent to that every Cauchy net (possibly indexed by a proper class) converges, so surreals aren't a complete_space by the mathlib definition.
However, if we restrict to Cauchy nets indexed by sets, these do converge, because they are all eventually constant! For any net f that is not eventually constant and i an element of the indexing set, {|f j - f k|}_{j,k ≥ i} contains a positive surreal ε_i, and the surreal ε = {0 | ε_i for all i in indexing set} is positive and smaller than all ε_i, i.e. for any i, there are some j, k ≥ i such that |f j - f k| > ε_i > ε, so f is not Cauchy. Therefore, we can say the surreals are "small-complete" in the uniform space sense (similar to the "conditional" completeness of ordinals and cardinals, and reminiscent of small-completeness in category theory.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:10):
Alright, I've got some time to spare!
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:15):
First question, what's up with mul_option
? Seems like a very ad-hoc definition and its lemmas are even worse
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:18):
Another complaint I want to get out of the way quickly: I don't think we should borrow the notation from the paper so literally. For someone just reading through mathlib
, it's going to seem very out of place that we use P1
, P2
, and P4
as the names of our prepositions (instead of P3
for the last one), and thm8
isn't going to make any sense either.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:19):
Oh wait, you do use P3
too, nevermind then
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:24):
Minor remark, I don't think you use abel
in the hydra file
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:24):
I'll PR the minor and uncontroversial changes from that file now, so that the final diff is smaller
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:32):
Reading through more of the PR, I think I see what purpose mul_option
plays. I guess it can stay, but it should either be made into a private, auxiliary definition, or if it has any potential of being useful outside of the surreal multiplication proof, it should have a good docstring explaining how that is
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:33):
I think the left_moves_mul_iff
and right_moves_mul_iff
lemmas should be made into induction principles rather than equivalences, kind of how I did on #14345. Also, it would be nice if the theorem names made reference to the fact you're working with games and not pre-games.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:35):
I don't think there's a need for le_of_forall_lt
. The lemmas le_of_forall_lf
and lt.lf
should get you there much more easily.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:37):
I wonder if is_option_neg
would be better stated as : is_option (-x) (-y) ↔ is_option x y
. What's the general strategy for these lemmas on negations where you can write it both ways? Surely the rest of mathlib has some tips here
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:38):
I think your proposal of making numeric
into a set should be its own separate PR. I'll give you the chance to do it, unless you want me to do it for you
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:40):
Minor typo: "because we needs show P1, P2..."
Junyan Xu (Jun 06 2022 at 19:42):
Thanks for taking a look! I just pushed further cleanup including docstring for mul_option. I'll address other comments later tonight if you haven't figured them out by then.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 19:43):
I was just about to say, the rest of the PR looks very very clean. It's amazing you managed to organize such a complicated statement in such a clean way!
Junyan Xu (Jun 06 2022 at 22:38):
Another complaint I want to get out of the way quickly: I don't think we should borrow the notation from the paper so literally. For someone just reading through mathlib, it's going to seem very out of place that we use P1, P2, and P4 as the names of our prepositions (instead of P3 for the last one), and thm8 isn't going to make any sense either.
With a detailed section docstring, I guess this should be okay? When working on a hard proof, you don't want to write very long names that are fully descriptive. Enclosing these lemmas/defs not supposed to be used elsewhere in a arcane namespace is enough to prevent clashing with these short names. Final results ready for consumption are extracted to the numeric
namespace, like mul_pos
(basically P3), mul_congr_left
(P2), and mul
(P1).
I don't think there's a need for le_of_forall_lt. The lemmas le_of_forall_lf and lt.lf should get you there much more easily.
docs#le_of_forall_lt already exists and takes the extraneous numeric
hypotheses, so I'm just removing those hypotheses and move it to game/pgame
.
I wonder if is_option_neg would be better stated as :
is_option (-x) (-y) ↔ is_option x y
.
It seems it's easier to use this way. You might experiment with the other way and see what it takes to fix everything. When making decisions about forms of lemmas (e.g. whether to take quotient into game
or not, e.g. in P2), I chose the form that makes the most proofs the shortest.
I think your proposal of making
numeric
into a set should be its own separate PR. I'll give you the chance to do it, unless you want me to do it for you
It's already done in this branch. If uncontroversial (I assume), might just go into mathlib with the same PR.
Regarding mul_option
, it would be easier to show left/right_moves_mul_iff
if we first prove the lemmas that the left options of the second kind/right options of both kinds are equivalent to (possibly negation of) mul_option
s.
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 23:08):
Alright, you've sold me on the P1 and such names, after all these are just auxiliary constructions
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 23:08):
I still think thm8
is a bad namespace name
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 23:09):
Why not something more descriptive like surreal_mul
? Not like we're going to use this namespace much anyways
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 23:11):
As for le_of_forall_lt
, I remember why I added it now. It makes working with surreals a tad easier. The lemma can and should stay, I'll move and golf it later today
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 23:12):
I do still think numeric
turning into a set should be a separate PR, since it has a very different aim and scope to the rest of this
Violeta Hernández (Jun 06 2022 at 23:13):
And for mul_option
, can you describe what the idea is? Want to make sure we're on the same track here
Junyan Xu (Jun 06 2022 at 23:34):
mul_option
is what makes the main idea (of exploiting symmetry) possible; because all left/right options of the surreal product are of the same form, whenever we want to prove a statement about those options, we can do it uniformly, by applying the same lemma. For example, the proof of P1 consists of four applications of mul_option_lt
, the proof of P2 consists of four applications of mul_option_lt_mul_of_equiv
, and the proof of P4 also requires four statements of the form mul_options_lt_mul
.
I envision that mul_option
might also be used to golf some existing proofs.
Will be back in 1.5-2 hours.
Junyan Xu (Jun 07 2022 at 02:21):
Alright I've renamed thm8
to surreal_mul
... and opened #14585 from branch#surreal_set (it also does some other stuff now).
Violeta Hernández (Jul 11 2022 at 18:29):
I'll attempt to redefine mul
in terms of mul_option
, see if that makes anything simpler
Violeta Hernández (Jul 11 2022 at 18:30):
I imagine we'll have to unfold
it to prove all the basic theorems, but it simplifies the surreal multiplication proof, then it should be a net gain
Violeta Hernández (Jul 11 2022 at 18:32):
By the way, I've taken many of the todos and improvements in your branch and PR'd them separately
Last updated: Dec 20 2023 at 11:08 UTC