2. Basics
This chapter is designed to introduce you to the nuts and bolts of mathematical reasoning in Lean: calculating, applying lemmas and theorems, and reasoning about generic structures.
2.1. Calculating
We generally learn to carry out mathematical calculations without thinking of them as proofs. But when we justify each step in a calculation, as Lean requires us to do, the net result is a proof that the left-hand side of the calculation is equal to the right-hand side.
In Lean, stating a theorem is tantamount to stating a goal,
namely, the goal of proving the theorem.
Lean provides the rewrite
tactic, abbreviated rw
,
to replace the left-hand side of an identity by the right-hand side
in the goal. If a
, b
, and c
are real numbers,
mul_assoc a b c
is the identity a * b * c = a * (b * c)
and mul_comm a b
is the identity a * b = b * a
.
Lean provides automation that generally eliminates the need
to refer the facts like these explicitly,
but they are useful for the purposes of illustration.
In Lean, multiplication associates to the left,
so the left-hand side of mul_assoc
could also be written (a * b) * c
.
However, it is generally good style to be mindful of Lean’s
notational conventions and leave out parentheses when Lean does as well.
Let’s try out rw
.
import data.real.basic
example (a b c : ℝ) : (a * b) * c = b * (a * c) :=
begin
rw mul_comm a b,
rw mul_assoc b a c
end
The import
line at the beginning of the example
imports the theory of the real numbers from mathlib
.
For the sake of brevity,
we generally suppress information like this when it
is repeated from example to example.
Clicking the try it!
button displays the full
example as it is meant to be processed and checked by Lean.
You are welcome to make changes to see what happens.
You can type the ℝ
character as \R
or \real
in VS Code.
The symbol doesn’t appear until you hit space or the tab key.
If you hover over a symbol when reading a Lean file,
VS Code will show you the syntax that can be used to enter it.
If your keyboard does not have an easily accessible backslash,
you can change the leading character by changing the
lean.input.leader
setting.
When a cursor is in the middle of a tactic proof, Lean reports on the current proof state in the Lean infoview window. As you move your cursor past each step of the proof, you can see the state change. A typical proof state in Lean might look as follows:
1 goal
x y : ℕ,
h₁ : prime x,
h₂ : ¬even x,
h₃ : y > x
⊢ y ≥ 4
The lines before the one that begins with ⊢
denote the context:
they are the objects and assumptions currently at play.
In this example, these include two objects, x
and y
,
each a natural number.
They also include three assumptions,
labelled h₁
, h₂
, and h₃
.
In Lean, everything in a context is labelled with an identifier.
You can type these subscripted labels as h\1
, h\2
, and h\3
,
but any legal identifiers would do:
you can use h1
, h2
, h3
instead,
or foo
, bar
, and baz
.
The last line represents the goal,
that is, the fact to be proved.
Sometimes people use target for the fact to be proved,
and goal for the combination of the context and the target.
In practice, the intended meaning is usually clear.
Try proving these identities,
in each case replacing sorry
by a tactic proof.
With the rw
tactic, you can use a left arrow (\l
)
to reverse an identity.
For example, rw ← mul_assoc a b c
replaces a * (b * c)
by a * b * c
in the current goal.
example (a b c : ℝ) : (c * b) * a = b * (a * c) :=
begin
sorry
end
example (a b c : ℝ) : a * (b * c) = b * (a * c) :=
begin
sorry
end
You can also use identities like mul_assoc
and mul_comm
without arguments.
In this case, the rewrite tactic tries to match the left-hand side with
an expression in the goal,
using the first pattern it finds.
example (a b c : ℝ) : a * b * c = b * c * a :=
begin
rw mul_assoc,
rw mul_comm
end
You can also provide partial information.
For example, mul_comm a
matches any pattern of the form
a * ?
and rewrites it to ? * a
.
Try doing the first of these examples without
providing any arguments at all,
and the second with only one argument.
example (a b c : ℝ) : a * (b * c) = b * (c * a) :=
begin
sorry
end
example (a b c : ℝ) : a * (b * c) = b * (a * c) :=
begin
sorry
end
You an also use rw
with facts from the local context.
example (a b c d e f : ℝ) (h : a * b = c * d) (h' : e = f) :
a * (b * e) = c * (d * f) :=
begin
rw h',
rw ←mul_assoc,
rw h,
rw mul_assoc
end
Try these:
example (a b c d e f : ℝ) (h : b * c = e * f) :
a * b * c * d = a * e * f * d :=
begin
sorry
end
example (a b c d : ℝ) (hyp : c = b * a - d) (hyp' : d = a * b) : c = 0 :=
begin
sorry
end
For the second one, you can use the theorem sub_self
,
where sub_self a
is the identity a - a = 0
.
We now introduce some useful features of Lean.
First, multiple rewrite commands can be carried out
with a single command,
by listing the relevant identities within square brackets.
Second, when a tactic proof is just a single command,
we can replace the begin ... end
block with a by
.
example (a b c d e f : ℝ) (h : a * b = c * d) (h' : e = f) :
a * (b * e) = c * (d * f) :=
by rw [h', ←mul_assoc, h, mul_assoc]
You still see the incremental progress by placing the cursor after a comma in any list of rewrites.
Another trick is that we can declare variables once and for all outside an example or theorem. When Lean sees them mentioned in the statement of the theorem, it includes them automatically.
variables a b c d e f g : ℝ
example (h : a * b = c * d) (h' : e = f) :
a * (b * e) = c * (d * f) :=
by rw [h', ←mul_assoc, h, mul_assoc]
Inspection of the tactic state at the beginning of the above proof
reveals that Lean indeed included the relevant variables, leaving out
g that doesn’t feature in the statement.
We can delimit the scope of the declaration by putting it
in a section ... end
block.
Finally, recall from the introduction that Lean provides us with a
command to determine the type of an expression:
section
variables a b c : ℝ
#check a
#check a + b
#check (a : ℝ)
#check mul_comm a b
#check (mul_comm a b : a * b = b * a)
#check mul_assoc c a b
#check mul_comm a
#check mul_comm
#check @mul_comm
end
The #check
command works for both objects and facts.
In response to the command #check a
, Lean reports that a
has type ℝ
.
In response to the command #check mul_comm a b
,
Lean reports that mul_comm a b
is a proof of the fact a * b = b * a
.
The command #check (a : ℝ)
states our expectation that the
type of a
is ℝ
,
and Lean will raise an error if that is not the case.
We will explain the output of the last three #check
commands later,
but in the meanwhile, you can take a look at them,
and experiment with some #check
commands of your own.
Let’s try some more examples. The theorem two_mul a
says
that 2 * a = a + a
. The theorems add_mul
and mul_add
express the distributivity of multiplication over addition,
and the theorem add_assoc
expresses the associativity of addition.
Use the #check
command to see the precise statements.
example : (a + b) * (a + b) = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b :=
begin
rw [mul_add, add_mul, add_mul],
rw [←add_assoc, add_assoc (a * a)],
rw [mul_comm b a, ←two_mul]
end
Whereas it is possible to figure out what it going on in this proof
by stepping through it in the editor,
it is hard to read on its own.
Lean provides a more structured way of writing proofs like this
using the calc
keyword.
example : (a + b) * (a + b) = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b :=
calc
(a + b) * (a + b)
= a * a + b * a + (a * b + b * b) :
by rw [mul_add, add_mul, add_mul]
... = a * a + (b * a + a * b) + b * b :
by rw [←add_assoc, add_assoc (a * a)]
... = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b :
by rw [mul_comm b a, ←two_mul]
Notice that there is no more begin ... end
block:
an expression that begins with calc
is a proof term.
A calc
expression can also be used inside a tactic proof,
but Lean interprets it as the instruction to use the resulting
proof term to solve the goal.
The calc
syntax is finicky: the dots and colons and justification
have to be in the format indicated above.
Lean ignores whitespace like spaces, tabs, and returns,
so you have some flexibility to make the calculation look more attractive.
One way to write a calc
proof is to outline it first
using the sorry
tactic for justification,
make sure Lean accepts the expression modulo these,
and then justify the individual steps using tactics.
example : (a + b) * (a + b) = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b :=
calc
(a + b) * (a + b)
= a * a + b * a + (a * b + b * b) :
begin
sorry
end
... = a * a + (b * a + a * b) + b * b : by sorry
... = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b : by sorry
Try proving the following identity using both a pure rw
proof
and a more structured calc
proof:
example : (a + b) * (c + d) = a * c + a * d + b * c + b * d :=
sorry
The following exercise is a little more challenging. You can use the theorems listed underneath.
example (a b : ℝ) : (a + b) * (a - b) = a^2 - b^2 :=
begin
sorry
end
#check pow_two a
#check mul_sub a b c
#check add_mul a b c
#check add_sub a b c
#check sub_sub a b c
#check add_zero a
We can also perform rewriting in an assumption in the context.
For example, rw mul_comm a b at hyp
replaces a * b
by b * a
in the assumption hyp
.
example (a b c d : ℝ) (hyp : c = d * a + b) (hyp' : b = a * d) :
c = 2 * a * d :=
begin
rw hyp' at hyp,
rw mul_comm d a at hyp,
rw ← two_mul (a * d) at hyp,
rw ← mul_assoc 2 a d at hyp,
exact hyp
end
In the last step, the exact
tactic can use hyp
to solve the goal
because at that point hyp
matches the goal exactly.
We close this section by noting that mathlib
provides a
useful bit of automation with a ring
tactic,
which is designed to prove identities in any commutative ring.
example : (c * b) * a = b * (a * c) :=
by ring
example : (a + b) * (a + b) = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b :=
by ring
example : (a + b) * (a - b) = a^2 - b^2 :=
by ring
example (hyp : c = d * a + b) (hyp' : b = a * d) :
c = 2 * a * d :=
begin
rw [hyp, hyp'],
ring
end
The ring
tactic is imported indirectly when we
import data.real.basic
,
but we will see in the next section that it can be used
for calculations on structures other than the real numbers.
It can be imported explicitly with the command
import tactic
.
We will see there are similar tactics for other common kind of algebraic
structures.
There is a variation of rw
called nth_rewrite
that allows you to replace only particular instances of an expression in the goal.
Possible matches are enumerated starting with zero,
so in the following example, nth_rewrite 1 h
replaces the second
occurrence of a + b
with c
.
example (a b c : ℕ) (h : a + b = c) : (a + b) * (a + b) = a * c + b * c :=
begin
nth_rewrite 1 h,
rw add_mul
end
See also nth_rewrite_lhs
and nth_rewrite_rhs
.
For a more sophisticated means of rewriting particular subexpressions,
see the documentation for the conversion tactic.
2.2. Proving Identities in Algebraic Structures
Mathematically, a ring consists of a collection of objects, \(R\), operations \(+\) \(\times\), and constants \(0\) and \(1\), and an operation \(x \mapsto -x\) such that:
\(R\) with \(+\) is an abelian group, with \(0\) as the additive identity and negation as inverse.
Multiplication is associative with identity \(1\), and multiplication distributes over addition.
In Lean, the collection of objects is represented as a type, R
.
The ring axioms are as follows:
variables (R : Type*) [ring R]
#check (add_assoc : ∀ a b c : R, a + b + c = a + (b + c))
#check (add_comm : ∀ a b : R, a + b = b + a)
#check (zero_add : ∀ a : R, 0 + a = a)
#check (add_left_neg : ∀ a : R, -a + a = 0)
#check (mul_assoc : ∀ a b c : R, a * b * c = a * (b * c))
#check (mul_one : ∀ a : R, a * 1 = a)
#check (one_mul : ∀ a : R, 1 * a = a)
#check (mul_add : ∀ a b c : R, a * (b + c) = a * b + a * c)
#check (add_mul : ∀ a b c : R, (a + b) * c = a * c + b * c)
You will learn more about the square brackets in the first line later,
but for the time being,
suffice it to say that the declaration gives us a type, R
,
and a ring structure on R
.
Lean then allows us to use generic ring notation with elements of R
,
and to make use of a library of theorems about rings.
The names of some of the theorems should look familiar:
they are exactly the ones we used to calculate with the real numbers
in the last section.
Lean is good not only for proving things about concrete mathematical
structures like the natural numbers and the integers,
but also for proving things about abstract structures,
characterized axiomatically, like rings.
Moreover, Lean supports generic reasoning about
both abstract and concrete structures,
and can be trained to recognized appropriate instances.
So any theorem about rings can be applied to concrete rings
like the integers, ℤ
, the rational numbers, ℚ
,
and the complex numbers ℂ
.
It can also be applied to any instance of an abstract
structure that extends rings,
such as any ordered ring or any field.
Not all important properties of the real numbers hold in an
arbitrary ring, however.
For example, multiplication on the real numbers
is commutative,
but that does not hold in general.
If you have taken a course in linear algebra,
you will recognize that, for every \(n\),
the \(n\) by \(n\) matrices of real numbers
form a ring in which commutativity usually fails. If we declare R
to be a
commutative ring, in fact, all the theorems
in the last section continue to hold when we replace
ℝ
by R
.
variables (R : Type*) [comm_ring R]
variables a b c d : R
example : (c * b) * a = b * (a * c) :=
by ring
example : (a + b) * (a + b) = a * a + 2 * (a * b) + b * b :=
by ring
example : (a + b) * (a - b) = a^2 - b^2 :=
by ring
example (hyp : c = d * a + b) (hyp' : b = a * d) :
c = 2 * a * d :=
begin
rw [hyp, hyp'],
ring
end
We leave it to you to check that all the other proofs go through unchanged.
The goal of this section is to strengthen the skills
you have developed in the last section
and apply them to reasoning axiomatically about rings.
We will start with the axioms listed above,
and use them to derive other facts.
Most of the facts we prove are already in mathlib
.
We will give the versions we prove the same names
to help you learn the contents of the library
as well as the naming conventions.
Lean provides an organizational mechanism similar
to those used in programming languages:
when a definition or theorem foo
is introduced in a namespace
bar
, its full name is bar.foo
.
The command open bar
later opens the namespace,
which allows us to use the shorter name foo
.
To avoid errors due to name clashes,
in the next example we put our versions of the library
theorems in a new namespace called my_ring.
The next example shows that we do not need add_zero
or add_right_neg
as ring axioms, because they follow from the other axioms.
namespace my_ring
variables {R : Type*} [ring R]
theorem add_zero (a : R) : a + 0 = a :=
by rw [add_comm, zero_add]
theorem add_right_neg (a : R) : a + -a = 0 :=
by rw [add_comm, add_left_neg]
#check @my_ring.add_zero
#check @add_zero
end my_ring
The net effect is that we can temporarily reprove a theorem in the library, and then go on using the library version after that. But don’t cheat! In the exercises that follow, take care to use only the general facts about rings that we have proved earlier in this section.
(If you are paying careful attention, you may have noticed that we
changed the round brackets in (R : Type*)
for
curly brackets in {R : Type*}
.
This declares R
to be an implicit argument.
We will explain what this means in a moment,
but don’t worry about it in the meanwhile.)
Here is a useful theorem:
theorem neg_add_cancel_left (a b : R) : -a + (a + b) = b :=
by rw [←add_assoc, add_left_neg, zero_add]
Prove the companion version:
theorem add_neg_cancel_right (a b : R) : (a + b) + -b = a :=
sorry
Use these to prove the following:
theorem add_left_cancel {a b c : R} (h : a + b = a + c) : b = c :=
sorry
theorem add_right_cancel {a b c : R} (h : a + b = c + b) : a = c :=
sorry
With enough planning, you can do each of them with three rewrites.
We can now explain the use of the curly braces.
Imagine you are in a situation where you have a
, b
, and c
in your context,
as well as a hypothesis h : a + b = a + c
,
and you would like to draw the conclusion b = c
.
In Lean, you can apply a theorem to hypotheses and facts just
the same way that you can apply them to objects,
so you might think that add_left_cancel a b c h
is a
proof of the fact b = c
.
But notice that explicitly writing a
, b
, and c
is redundant, because the hypothesis h
makes it clear that
those are the objects we have in mind.
In this case, typing a few extra characters is not onerous,
but if we wanted to apply add_left_cancel
to more complicated expressions,
writing them would be tedious.
In cases like these,
Lean allows us to mark arguments as implicit,
meaning that they are supposed to be left out and inferred by other means,
such as later arguments and hypotheses.
The curly brackets in {a b c : R}
do exactly that.
So, given the statement of the theorem above,
the correct expression is simply add_left_cancel h
.
To illustrate, let us show that a * 0 = 0
follows from the ring axioms.
theorem mul_zero (a : R) : a * 0 = 0 :=
begin
have h : a * 0 + a * 0 = a * 0 + 0,
{ rw [←mul_add, add_zero, add_zero] },
rw add_left_cancel h
end
We have used a new trick!
If you step through the proof,
you can see what is going on.
The have
tactic introduces a new goal,
a * 0 + a * 0 = a * 0 + 0
,
with the same context as the original goal.
In the next line, we could have omitted the curly brackets,
which serve as an inner begin ... end
pair.
Using them promotes a modular style of proof:
the part of the proof inside the brackets establishes the goal
that was introduced by the have
.
After that, we are back to proving the original goal,
except a new hypothesis h
has been added:
having proved it, we are now free to use it.
At this point, the goal is exactly the result of add_left_cancel h
.
We could equally well have closed the proof with
apply add_left_cancel h
or exact add_left_cancel h
.
Remember that multiplication is not assumed to be commutative, so the following theorem also requires some work.
theorem zero_mul (a : R) : 0 * a = 0 :=
sorry
By now, you should also be able replace each sorry
in the next
exercise with a proof,
still using only facts about rings that we have
established in this section.
theorem neg_eq_of_add_eq_zero {a b : R} (h : a + b = 0) : -a = b :=
sorry
theorem eq_neg_of_add_eq_zero {a b : R} (h : a + b = 0) : a = -b :=
sorry
theorem neg_zero : (-0 : R) = 0 :=
begin
apply neg_eq_of_add_eq_zero,
rw add_zero
end
theorem neg_neg (a : R) : -(-a) = a :=
sorry
We had to use the annotation (-0 : R)
instead of 0
in the third theorem
because without specifying R
it is impossible for Lean to infer which 0
we have in mind,
and by default it would be interpreted as a natural number.
In Lean, subtraction in a ring is provably equal to addition of the additive inverse.
example (a b : R) : a - b = a + -b :=
sub_eq_add_neg a b
On the real numbers, it is defined that way:
example (a b : ℝ) : a - b = a + -b :=
rfl
example (a b : ℝ) : a - b = a + -b :=
by reflexivity
The proof term rfl
is short for reflexivity
.
Presenting it as a proof of a - b = a + -b
forces Lean
to unfold the definition and recognize both sides as being the same.
The reflexivity
tactic, which can be abbreviated as refl
,
does the same.
This is an instance of what is known as a definitional equality
in Lean’s underlying logic.
This means that not only can one rewrite with sub_eq_add_neg
to replace a - b = a + -b
,
but in some contexts, when dealing with the real numbers,
you can use the two sides of the equation interchangeably.
For example, you now have enough information to prove the theorem
self_sub
from the last section:
theorem self_sub (a : R) : a - a = 0 :=
sorry
Show that you can prove this using rw
,
but if you replace the arbitrary ring R
by
the real numbers, you can also prove it
using either apply
or exact
.
For another example of definitional equality,
Lean knows that 1 + 1 = 2
holds in any ring.
With a bit of effort,
you can use that to prove the theorem two_mul
from
the last section:
lemma one_add_one_eq_two : 1 + 1 = (2 : R) :=
by refl
theorem two_mul (a : R) : 2 * a = a + a :=
sorry
We close this section by noting that some of the facts about addition and negation that we established above do not need the full strength of the ring axioms, or even commutativity of addition. The weaker notion of a group can be axiomatized as follows:
variables (A : Type*) [add_group A]
#check (add_assoc : ∀ a b c : A, a + b + c = a + (b + c))
#check (zero_add : ∀ a : A, 0 + a = a)
#check (add_left_neg : ∀ a : A, -a + a = 0)
It is conventional to use additive notation when
the group operation is commutative,
and multiplicative notation otherwise.
So Lean defines a multiplicative version as well as the
additive version (and also their abelian variants,
add_comm_group
and comm_group
).
variables {G : Type*} [group G]
#check (mul_assoc : ∀ a b c : G, a * b * c = a * (b * c))
#check (one_mul : ∀ a : G, 1 * a = a)
#check (mul_left_inv : ∀ a : G, a⁻¹ * a = 1)
If you are feeling cocky, try proving the following facts about groups, using only these axioms. You will need to prove a number of helper lemmas along the way. The proofs we have carried out in this section provide some hints.
theorem mul_right_inv (a : G) : a * a⁻¹ = 1 :=
sorry
theorem mul_one (a : G) : a * 1 = a :=
sorry
theorem mul_inv_rev (a b : G) : (a * b)⁻¹ = b⁻¹ * a ⁻¹ :=
sorry
Explicitly invoking those lemmas is tedious, so mathlib provides tactics similar to ring in order to cover most uses: group is for non-commutative multiplicative groups, abel for abelian additive groups, and noncomm_ring for non-commutative groups. It may seem odd that the algebraic structures are called ring and comm_ring while the tactics are named noncomm_ring and ring. This is partly for historical reasons, but also for the convenience of using a shorter name for the tactic that deals with commutative rings, since it is used more often.
2.3. Using Theorems and Lemmas
Rewriting is great for proving equations,
but what about other sorts of theorems?
For example, how can we prove an inequality,
like the fact that \(a + e^b \le a + e^c\) holds whenever \(b \le c\)?
We have already seen that theorems can be applied to arguments and hypotheses,
and that the apply
and exact
tactics can be used to solve goals.
In this section, we will make good use of these tools.
Consider the library theorems le_refl
and le_trans
:
#check (le_refl : ∀ a : ℝ, a ≤ a)
#check (le_trans : a ≤ b → b ≤ c → a ≤ c)
As we explain in more detail in Section 3.1,
the implicit parentheses in the statement of le_trans
associate to the right, so it should be interpreted as a ≤ b → (b ≤ c → a ≤ c)
.
The library designers have set the arguments to le_trans
implicit,
so that Lean will not let you provide them explicitly (unless you
really insist, as we will discuss later).
Rather, it expects to infer them from the context in which they are used.
For example, when hypotheses h : a ≤ b
and h' : b ≤ c
are in the context,
all the following work:
variables (h : a ≤ b) (h' : b ≤ c)
#check (le_refl : ∀ a : real, a ≤ a)
#check (le_refl a : a ≤ a)
#check (le_trans : a ≤ b → b ≤ c → a ≤ c)
#check (le_trans h : b ≤ c → a ≤ c)
#check (le_trans h h' : a ≤ c)
The apply
tactic takes a proof of a general statement or implication,
tries to match the conclusion with the current goal,
and leaves the hypotheses, if any, as new goals.
If the given proof matches the goal exactly
(modulo definitional equality),
you can use the exact
tactic instead of apply
.
So, all of these work:
example (x y z : ℝ) (h₀ : x ≤ y) (h₁ : y ≤ z) : x ≤ z :=
begin
apply le_trans,
{ apply h₀ },
apply h₁
end
example (x y z : ℝ) (h₀ : x ≤ y) (h₁ : y ≤ z) : x ≤ z :=
begin
apply le_trans h₀,
apply h₁
end
example (x y z : ℝ) (h₀ : x ≤ y) (h₁ : y ≤ z) : x ≤ z :=
by exact le_trans h₀ h₁
example (x y z : ℝ) (h₀ : x ≤ y) (h₁ : y ≤ z) : x ≤ z :=
le_trans h₀ h₁
example (x : ℝ) : x ≤ x :=
by apply le_refl
example (x : ℝ) : x ≤ x :=
by exact le_refl x
example (x : ℝ) : x ≤ x :=
le_refl x
In the first example, applying le_trans
creates two goals,
and we use the curly braces to enclose the proof
of the first one.
In the fourth example and in the last example,
we avoid going into tactic mode entirely:
le_trans h₀ h₁
and le_refl x
are the proof terms we need.
Here are a few more library theorems:
#check (le_refl : ∀ a, a ≤ a)
#check (le_trans : a ≤ b → b ≤ c → a ≤ c)
#check (lt_of_le_of_lt : a ≤ b → b < c → a < c)
#check (lt_of_lt_of_le : a < b → b ≤ c → a < c)
#check (lt_trans : a < b → b < c → a < c)
Use them together with apply
and exact
to prove the following:
example (h₀ : a ≤ b) (h₁ : b < c) (h₂ : c ≤ d)
(h₃ : d < e) :
a < e :=
sorry
In fact, Lean has a tactic that does this sort of thing automatically:
example (h₀ : a ≤ b) (h₁ : b < c) (h₂ : c ≤ d)
(h₃ : d < e) :
a < e :=
by linarith
The linarith
tactic is designed to handle linear arithmetic.
example (h : 2 * a ≤ 3 * b) (h' : 1 ≤ a) (h'' : d = 2) :
d + a ≤ 5 * b :=
by linarith
In addition to equations and inequalities in the context,
linarith
will use additional inequalities that you pass as arguments.
In the next example, exp_le_exp.mpr h'
is a proof of
exp b ≤ exp c
, as we will explain in a moment.
Notice that, in Lean, we write f x
to denote the application
of a function f
to the argument x
,
exactly the same way we write h x
to denote the result of
applying a fact or theorem h
to the argument x
.
Parentheses are only needed for compound arguments,
as in f (x + y)
. Without the parentheses, f x + y
would be parsed as (f x) + y
.
example (h : 1 ≤ a) (h' : b ≤ c) :
2 + a + exp b ≤ 3 * a + exp c :=
by linarith [exp_le_exp.mpr h']
Here are some more theorems in the library that can be used to establish inequalities on the real numbers.
#check (exp_le_exp : exp a ≤ exp b ↔ a ≤ b)
#check (exp_lt_exp : exp a < exp b ↔ a < b)
#check (log_le_log : 0 < a → 0 < b → (log a ≤ log b ↔ a ≤ b))
#check (log_lt_log : 0 < a → a < b → log a < log b)
#check (add_le_add : a ≤ b → c ≤ d → a + c ≤ b + d)
#check (add_le_add_left : a ≤ b → ∀ c, c + a ≤ c + b)
#check (add_le_add_right : a ≤ b → ∀ c, a + c ≤ b + c)
#check (add_lt_add_of_le_of_lt : a ≤ b → c < d → a + c < b + d)
#check (add_lt_add_of_lt_of_le : a < b → c ≤ d → a + c < b + d)
#check (add_lt_add_left : a < b → ∀ c, c + a < c + b)
#check (add_lt_add_right : a < b → ∀ c, a + c < b + c)
#check (add_nonneg : 0 ≤ a → 0 ≤ b → 0 ≤ a + b)
#check (add_pos : 0 < a → 0 < b → 0 < a + b)
#check (add_pos_of_pos_of_nonneg : 0 < a → 0 ≤ b → 0 < a + b)
#check (exp_pos : ∀ a, 0 < exp a)
#check @add_le_add_left
Some of the theorems, exp_le_exp
, exp_lt_exp
, and log_le_log
use a bi-implication, which represents the
phrase “if and only if.”
(You can type it in VS Code with \lr
of \iff
).
We will discuss this connective in greater detail in the next chapter.
Such a theorem can be used with rw
to rewrite a goal to
an equivalent one:
example (h : a ≤ b) : exp a ≤ exp b :=
begin
rw exp_le_exp,
exact h
end
In this section, however, we will use the fact that if h : A ↔ B
is such an equivalence,
then h.mp
establishes the forward direction, A → B
,
and h.mpr
establishes the reverse direction, B → A
.
Here, mp
stands for “modus ponens” and
mpr
stands for “modus ponens reverse.”
You can also use h.1
and h.2
for h.mp
and h.mpr
,
respectively, if you prefer.
Thus the following proof works:
example (h₀ : a ≤ b) (h₁ : c < d) : a + exp c + e < b + exp d + e :=
begin
apply add_lt_add_of_lt_of_le,
{ apply add_lt_add_of_le_of_lt h₀,
apply exp_lt_exp.mpr h₁ },
apply le_refl
end
The first line, apply add_lt_add_of_lt_of_le
,
creates two goals,
and once again we use the curly brackets to separate the
proof of the first from the proof of the second.
Try the following examples on your own.
The example in the middle shows you that the norm_num
tactic can be used to solve concrete numeric goals.
example (h₀ : d ≤ e) : c + exp (a + d) ≤ c + exp (a + e) :=
begin
sorry
end
example : (0 : ℝ) < 1 :=
by norm_num
example (h : a ≤ b) : log (1 + exp a) ≤ log (1 + exp b) :=
begin
have h₀ : 0 < 1 + exp a,
{ sorry },
have h₁ : 0 < 1 + exp b,
{ sorry },
apply (log_le_log h₀ h₁).mpr,
sorry
end
From these examples, it should be clear that being able to find the library theorems you need constitutes an important part of formalization. There are a number of strategies you can use:
You can browse mathlib in its GitHub repository.
You can use the API documentation on the mathlib web pages.
You can rely on mathlib naming conventions and tab completion in the editor to guess a theorem name. In Lean, a theorem named
A_of_B_of_C
establishes something of the formA
from hypotheses of the formB
andC
, whereA
,B
, andC
approximate the way we might read the goals out loud. So a theorem establishing something likex + y ≤ ...
will probably start withadd_le
. Typingadd_le
and hitting tab will give you some helpful choices.If you right-click on an existing theorem name in VS Code, the editor will show a menu with the option to jump to the file where the theorem is defined, and you can find similar theorems nearby.
You can use the
library_search
tactic, which tries to find the relevant theorem in the library.
example : 0 ≤ a^2 :=
begin
-- library_search,
exact pow_two_nonneg a
end
To try out library_search
in this example,
delete the exact
command and uncomment the previous line.
If you replace library_search
with suggest
,
you’ll see a long list of suggestions.
In this case, the suggestions are not helpful, but in other cases
it does better.
Using these tricks,
see if you can find what you need to do the
next example:
example (h : a ≤ b) : c - exp b ≤ c - exp a :=
sorry
Using the same tricks, confirm that linarith
instead of library_search
can also finish the job.
Here is another example of an inequality:
example : 2*a*b ≤ a^2 + b^2 :=
begin
have h : 0 ≤ a^2 - 2*a*b + b^2,
calc
a^2 - 2*a*b + b^2 = (a - b)^2 : by ring
... ≥ 0 : by apply pow_two_nonneg,
calc
2*a*b
= 2*a*b + 0 : by ring
... ≤ 2*a*b + (a^2 - 2*a*b + b^2) : add_le_add (le_refl _) h
... = a^2 + b^2 : by ring
end
Mathlib tends to put spaces around binary operations like *
and ^
,
but in this example, the more compressed format increases readability.
There are a number of things worth noticing.
First, an expression s ≥ t
is definitionally equivalent to t ≤ s
.
In principle, this means one should be able to use them interchangeably.
But some of Lean’s automation does not recognize the equivalence,
so mathlib tends to favor ≤
over ≥
.
Second, we have used the ring
tactic extensively.
It is a real timesaver!
Finally, notice that in the second line of the
second calc
proof,
instead of writing by exact add_le_add (le_refl _) h
,
we can simply write the proof term add_le_add (le_refl _) h
.
In fact, the only cleverness in the proof above is figuring
out the hypothesis h
.
Once we have it, the second calculation involves only
linear arithmetic, and linarith
can handle it:
example : 2*a*b ≤ a^2 + b^2 :=
begin
have h : 0 ≤ a^2 - 2*a*b + b^2,
calc
a^2 - 2*a*b + b^2 = (a - b)^2 : by ring
... ≥ 0 : by apply pow_two_nonneg,
linarith
end
How nice! We challenge you to use these ideas to prove the
following theorem. You can use the theorem abs_le'.mpr
.
example : abs (a*b) ≤ (a^2 + b^2) / 2 :=
sorry
#check abs_le'.mpr
If you managed to solve this, congratulations! You are well on your way to becoming a master formalizer.
2.4. More on Order and Divisibility
The min
function on the real numbers is uniquely characterized
by the following three facts:
#check (min_le_left a b : min a b ≤ a)
#check (min_le_right a b : min a b ≤ b)
#check (le_min : c ≤ a → c ≤ b → c ≤ min a b)
Can you guess the names of the theorems that characterize
max
in a similar way?
Notice that we have to apply min
to a pair of arguments a
and b
by writing min a b
rather than min (a, b)
.
Formally, min
is a function of type ℝ → ℝ → ℝ
.
When we write a type like this with multiple arrows,
the convention is that the implicit parentheses associate
to the right, so the type is interpreted as ℝ → (ℝ → ℝ)
.
The net effect is that if a
and b
have type ℝ
then min a
has type ℝ → ℝ
and
min a b
has type ℝ
, so min
acts like a function
of two arguments, as we expect. Handling multiple
arguments in this way is known as currying,
after the logician Haskell Curry.
The order of operations in Lean can also take some getting used to.
Function application binds tighter than infix operations, so the
expression min a b + c
is interpreted as (min a b) + c
.
With time, these conventions will become second nature.
Using the theorem le_antisymm
, we can show that two
real numbers are equal if each is less than or equal to the other.
Using this and the facts above,
we can show that min
is commutative:
example : min a b = min b a :=
begin
apply le_antisymm,
{ show min a b ≤ min b a,
apply le_min,
{ apply min_le_right },
apply min_le_left },
{ show min b a ≤ min a b,
apply le_min,
{ apply min_le_right },
apply min_le_left }
end
Here we have used curly brackets to separate proofs of
different goals.
Our usage is inconsistent:
at the outer level,
we use curly brackets and indentation for both goals,
whereas for the nested proofs,
we use curly brackets only until a single goal remains.
Both conventions are reasonable and useful.
We also use the show
tactic to structure
the proof
and indicate what is being proved in each block.
The proof still works without the show
commands,
but using them makes the proof easier to read and maintain.
It may bother you that the the proof is repetitive. To foreshadow skills you will learn later on, we note that one way to avoid the repetition is to state a local lemma and then use it:
example : min a b = min b a :=
begin
have h : ∀ x y, min x y ≤ min y x,
{ intros x y,
apply le_min,
apply min_le_right,
apply min_le_left },
apply le_antisymm, apply h, apply h
end
We will say more about the universal quantifier in
Section 3.1,
but suffice it to say here that the hypothesis
h
says that the desired inequality holds for
any x
and y
,
and the intros
tactic introduces an arbitrary
x
and y
to establish the conclusion.
The first apply
after le_antisymm
implicitly
uses h a b
, whereas the second one uses h b a
.
Another solution is to use the repeat
tactic,
which applies a tactic (or a block) as many times
as it can.
example : min a b = min b a :=
begin
apply le_antisymm,
repeat {
apply le_min,
apply min_le_right,
apply min_le_left }
end
In any case, whether or not you use these tricks, we encourage you to prove the following:
example : max a b = max b a :=
sorry
example : min (min a b) c = min a (min b c) :=
sorry
Of course, you are welcome to prove the associativity of max
as well.
It is an interesting fact that min
distributes over max
the way that multiplication distributes over addition,
and vice-versa.
In other words, on the real numbers, we have the identity
min a (max b c) ≤ max (min a b) (min a c)
as well as the corresponding version with max
and min
switched.
But in the next section we will see that this does not follow
from the transitivity and reflexivity of ≤
and
the characterizing properties of min
and max
enumerated above.
We need to use the fact that ≤
on the real numbers is a total order,
which is to say,
it satisfies ∀ x y, x ≤ y ∨ y ≤ x
.
Here the disjunction symbol, ∨
, represents “or”.
In the first case, we have min x y = x
,
and in the second case, we have min x y = y
.
We will learn how to reason by cases in Section 3.5,
but for now we will stick to examples that don’t require the case split.
Here is one such example:
lemma aux : min a b + c ≤ min (a + c) (b + c) :=
sorry
example : min a b + c = min (a + c) (b + c) :=
sorry
It is clear that aux
provides one of the two inequalities
needed to prove the equality,
but applying it to suitable values yields the other direction
as well.
As a hint, you can use the theorem add_neg_cancel_right
and the linarith
tactic.
Lean’s naming convention is made manifest in the library’s name for the triangle inequality:
#check (abs_add : ∀ a b : ℝ, abs (a + b) ≤ abs a + abs b)
Use it to prove the following variant:
example : abs a - abs b ≤ abs (a - b) :=
sorry
See if you can do this in three lines or less.
You can use the theorem sub_add_cancel
.
Another important relation that we will make use of
in the sections to come is the divisibility relation
on the natural numbers, x ∣ y
.
Be careful: the divisibility symbol is not the
ordinary bar on your keyboard.
Rather, it is a unicode character obtained by
typing \|
in VS Code.
By convention, mathlib uses dvd
to refer to it in theorem names.
example (h₀ : x ∣ y) (h₁ : y ∣ z) : x ∣ z :=
dvd_trans h₀ h₁
example : x ∣ y * x * z :=
begin
apply dvd_mul_of_dvd_left,
apply dvd_mul_left
end
example : x ∣ x^2 :=
by apply dvd_mul_right
In the last example, the exponent is a natural
number, and applying dvd_mul_right
forces Lean to expand the definition of x^2
to
x^1 * x
.
See if you can guess the names of the theorems
you need to prove the following:
example (h : x ∣ w) : x ∣ y * (x * z) + x^2 + w^2 :=
sorry
With respect to divisibility, the greatest common divisor,
gcd
, and least common multiple, lcm
,
are analogous to min
and max
.
Since every number divides 0
,
0
is really the greatest element with respect to divisibility:
variables m n : ℕ
open nat
#check (gcd_zero_right n : gcd n 0 = n)
#check (gcd_zero_left n : gcd 0 n = n)
#check (lcm_zero_right n : lcm n 0 = 0)
#check (lcm_zero_left n : lcm 0 n = 0)
The functions gcd
and lcm
for natural numbers are in the
nat
namespace,
which means that the full identifiers are nat.gcd
and nat.lcm
.
Similarly, the names of the theorems listed are prefixed by nat
.
The command open nat
opens the namespace,
allowing us to use the shorter names.
See if you can guess the names of the theorems you will need to prove the following:
example : gcd m n = gcd n m :=
sorry
Hint: you can use dvd_antisymm
.
2.5. Proving Facts about Algebraic Structures
In Section 2.2,
we saw that many common identities governing the real numbers hold
in more general classes of algebraic structures,
such as commutative rings.
We can use any axioms we want to describe an algebraic structure,
not just equations.
For example, a partial order consists of a set with a
binary relation that is reflexive and transitive,
like ≤
on the real numbers.
Lean knows about partial orders:
variables {α : Type*} [partial_order α]
variables x y z : α
#check x ≤ y
#check (le_refl x : x ≤ x)
#check (le_trans : x ≤ y → y ≤ z → x ≤ z)
Here we are adopting the mathlib convention of using
letters like α
, β
, and γ
(entered as \a
, \b
, and \g
)
for arbitrary types.
The library often uses letters like R
and G
for the carries of algebraic structures like rings and groups,
respectively,
but in general Greek letters are used for types,
especially when there is little or no structure
associated with them.
Associated to any partial order, ≤
,
there is also a strict partial order, <
,
which acts somewhat like <
on the real numbers.
Saying that x
is less than y
in this order
is equivalent to saying that it is less-than-or-equal to y
and not equal to y
.
#check x < y
#check (lt_irrefl x : ¬ x < x)
#check (lt_trans : x < y → y < z → x < z)
#check (lt_of_le_of_lt : x ≤ y → y < z → x < z)
#check (lt_of_lt_of_le : x < y → y ≤ z → x < z)
example : x < y ↔ x ≤ y ∧ x ≠ y :=
lt_iff_le_and_ne
In this example, the symbol ∧
stands for “and,”
the symbol ¬
stands for “not,” and
x ≠ y
abbreviates ¬ (x = y)
.
In Chapter 3, you will learn how to use
these logical connectives to prove that <
has the properties indicated.
A lattice is a structure that extends a partial
order with operations ⊓
and ⊔
that are
analogous to min
and max
on the real numbers:
variables {α : Type*} [lattice α]
variables x y z : α
#check x ⊓ y
#check (inf_le_left : x ⊓ y ≤ x)
#check (inf_le_right : x ⊓ y ≤ y)
#check (le_inf : z ≤ x → z ≤ y → z ≤ x ⊓ y)
#check x ⊔ y
#check (le_sup_left : x ≤ x ⊔ y)
#check (le_sup_right: y ≤ x ⊔ y)
#check (sup_le : x ≤ z → y ≤ z → x ⊔ y ≤ z)
The characterizations of ⊓
and ⊔
justify calling them
the greatest lower bound and least upper bound, respectively.
You can type them in VS code using \glb
and \lub
.
The symbols are also often called then infimum and
the supremum,
and mathlib refers to them as inf
and sup
in
theorem names.
To further complicate matters,
they are also often called meet and join.
Therefore, if you work with lattices,
you have to keep the following dictionary in mind:
⊓
is the greatest lower bound, infimum, or meet.⊔
is the least upper bound, supremum, or join.
Some instances of lattices include:
min
andmax
on any total order, such as the integers or real numbers with≤
∩
and∪
on the collection of subsets of some domain, with the ordering⊆
∧
and∨
on boolean truth values, with orderingx ≤ y
if eitherx
is false ory
is truegcd
andlcm
on the natural numbers (or positive natural numbers), with the divisibility ordering,∣
the collection of linear subspaces of a vector space, where the greatest lower bound is given by the intersection, the least upper bound is given by the sum of the two spaces, and the ordering is inclusion
the collection of topologies on a set (or, in Lean, a type), where the greatest lower bound of two topologies consists of the topology that is generated by their union, the least upper bound is their intersection, and the ordering is reverse inclusion
You can check that, as with min
/ max
and gcd
/ lcm
,
you can prove the commutativity and associativity of the infimum and supremum
using only their characterizing axioms,
together with le_refl
and le_trans
.
example : x ⊓ y = y ⊓ x := sorry
example : x ⊓ y ⊓ z = x ⊓ (y ⊓ z) := sorry
example : x ⊔ y = y ⊔ x := sorry
example : x ⊔ y ⊔ z = x ⊔ (y ⊔ z) := sorry
You can find these theorems in the mathlib as inf_comm
, inf_assoc
,
sup_comm
, and sup_assoc
, respectively.
Another good exercise is to prove the absorption laws using only those axioms:
theorem absorb1 : x ⊓ (x ⊔ y) = x := sorry
theorem absorb2 : x ⊔ (x ⊓ y) = x := sorry
These can be found in mathlib with the names inf_sup_self
and sup_inf_self
.
A lattice that satisfies the additional identities
x ⊓ (y ⊔ z) = (x ⊓ y) ⊔ (x ⊓ z)
and
x ⊔ (y ⊓ z) = (x ⊔ y) ⊓ (x ⊔ z)
is called a distributive lattice. Lean knows about these too:
variables {α : Type*} [distrib_lattice α]
variables x y z : α
#check (inf_sup_left : x ⊓ (y ⊔ z) = (x ⊓ y) ⊔ (x ⊓ z))
#check (inf_sup_right : (x ⊔ y) ⊓ z = (x ⊓ z) ⊔ (y ⊓ z))
#check (sup_inf_left : x ⊔ (y ⊓ z) = (x ⊔ y) ⊓ (x ⊔ z))
#check (sup_inf_right : (x ⊓ y) ⊔ z = (x ⊔ z) ⊓ (y ⊔ z))
The left and right versions are easily shown to be
equivalent, given the commutativity of ⊓
and ⊔
.
It is a good exercise to show that not every lattice
is distributive
by providing an explicit description of a
nondistributive lattice with finitely many elements.
It is also a good exercise to show that in any lattice,
either distributivity law implies the other:
variables {α : Type*} [lattice α]
variables a b c : α
example (h : ∀ x y z : α, x ⊓ (y ⊔ z) = (x ⊓ y) ⊔ (x ⊓ z)) :
a ⊔ (b ⊓ c) = (a ⊔ b) ⊓ (a ⊔ c) :=
sorry
example (h : ∀ x y z : α, x ⊔ (y ⊓ z) = (x ⊔ y) ⊓ (x ⊔ z)) :
a ⊓ (b ⊔ c) = (a ⊓ b) ⊔ (a ⊓ c) :=
sorry
It is possible to combine axiomatic structures into larger ones. For example, a strict ordered ring consists of a commutative ring together with a partial order on the carrier satisfying additional axioms that say that the ring operations are compatible with the order:
variables {R : Type*} [strict_ordered_ring R]
variables a b c : R
#check (add_le_add_left : a ≤ b → ∀ c, c + a ≤ c + b)
#check (mul_pos : 0 < a → 0 < b → 0 < a * b)
Chapter 3 will provide the means to derive the following from mul_pos
and the definition of <
:
#check (mul_nonneg : 0 ≤ a → 0 ≤ b → 0 ≤ a * b)
It is then an extended exercise to show that many common facts used to reason about arithmetic and the ordering on the real numbers hold generically for any ordered ring. Here are a couple of examples you can try, using only properties of rings, partial orders, and the facts enumerated in the last two examples:
example : a ≤ b → 0 ≤ b - a := sorry
example : 0 ≤ b - a → a ≤ b := sorry
example (h : a ≤ b) (h' : 0 ≤ c) : a * c ≤ b * c := sorry
Finally, here is one last example.
A metric space consists of a set equipped with a notion of
distance, dist x y
,
mapping any pair of elements to a real number.
The distance function is assumed to satisfy the following axioms:
variables {X : Type*} [metric_space X]
variables x y z : X
#check (dist_self x : dist x x = 0)
#check (dist_comm x y : dist x y = dist y x)
#check (dist_triangle x y z : dist x z ≤ dist x y + dist y z)
Having mastered this section, you can show that it follows from these axioms that distances are always nonnegative:
example (x y : X) : 0 ≤ dist x y := sorry
We recommend making use of the theorem nonneg_of_mul_nonneg_left
.
As you may have guessed, this theorem is called dist_nonneg
in mathlib.