Intermediate Value Theorem #
In this file we prove the Intermediate Value Theorem: if f : α → β
is a function defined on a
connected set s
that takes both values ≤ a
and values ≥ a
on s
, then it is equal to a
at
some point of s
. We also prove that intervals in a dense conditionally complete order are
preconnected and any preconnected set is an interval. Then we specialize IVT to functions continuous
on intervals.
Main results #
IsPreconnected_I??
: all intervalsI??
are preconnected,IsPreconnected.intermediate_value
,intermediate_value_univ
: Intermediate Value Theorem for connected sets and connected spaces, respectively;intermediate_value_Icc
,intermediate_value_Icc'
: Intermediate Value Theorem for functions on closed intervals.
Miscellaneous facts #
IsClosed.Icc_subset_of_forall_mem_nhdsWithin
: “Continuous induction” principle; ifs ∩ [a, b]
is closed,a ∈ s
, and for eachx ∈ [a, b) ∩ s
some of its right neighborhoods is includeds
, then[a, b] ⊆ s
.IsClosed.Icc_subset_of_forall_exists_gt
,IsClosed.mem_of_ge_of_forall_exists_gt
: two other versions of the “continuous induction” principle.ContinuousOn.StrictMonoOn_of_InjOn_Ioo
: Every continuous injectivef : (a, b) → δ
is strictly monotone or antitone (increasing or decreasing).
Tags #
intermediate value theorem, connected space, connected set
Intermediate value theorem on a (pre)connected space #
In this section we prove the following theorem (see IsPreconnected.intermediate_value₂
): if f
and g
are two functions continuous on a preconnected set s
, f a ≤ g a
at some a ∈ s
and
g b ≤ f b
at some b ∈ s
, then f c = g c
at some c ∈ s
. We prove several versions of this
statement, including the classical IVT that corresponds to a constant function g
.
Intermediate value theorem for two functions: if f
and g
are two continuous functions
on a preconnected space and f a ≤ g a
and g b ≤ f b
, then for some x
we have f x = g x
.
Intermediate value theorem for two functions: if f
and g
are two functions continuous
on a preconnected set s
and for some a b ∈ s
we have f a ≤ g a
and g b ≤ f b
,
then for some x ∈ s
we have f x = g x
.
Intermediate Value Theorem for continuous functions on connected sets.
Intermediate Value Theorem for continuous functions on connected spaces.
Intermediate Value Theorem for continuous functions on connected spaces.
(Pre)connected sets in a linear order #
In this section we prove the following results:
IsPreconnected.ordConnected
: any preconnected sets
in a linear order isOrdConnected
, i.e.a ∈ s
andb ∈ s
implyIcc a b ⊆ s
;IsPreconnected.mem_intervals
: any preconnected sets
in a conditionally complete linear order is one of the intervalsSet.Icc
,set.
Ico,
set.Ioc,
set.Ioo, ``Set.Ici
,Set.Iic
,Set.Ioi
,Set.Iio
; note that this is false for non-complete orders: e.g., inℝ \ {0}
, the set of positive numbers cannot be represented asSet.Ioi _
.
If a preconnected set contains endpoints of an interval, then it includes the whole interval.
If a preconnected set contains endpoints of an interval, then it includes the whole interval.
If preconnected set in a linear order space is unbounded below and above, then it is the whole space.
A bounded connected subset of a conditionally complete linear order includes the open interval
(Inf s, Sup s)
.
A preconnected set in a conditionally complete linear order is either one of the intervals
[Inf s, Sup s]
, [Inf s, Sup s)
, (Inf s, Sup s]
, (Inf s, Sup s)
, [Inf s, +∞)
,
(Inf s, +∞)
, (-∞, Sup s]
, (-∞, Sup s)
, (-∞, +∞)
, or ∅
. The converse statement requires
α
to be densely ordered.
A preconnected set is either one of the intervals Icc
, Ico
, Ioc
, Ioo
, Ici
, Ioi
,
Iic
, Iio
, or univ
, or ∅
. The converse statement requires α
to be densely ordered. Though
one can represent ∅
as (Inf ∅, Inf ∅)
, we include it into the list of possible cases to improve
readability.
Intervals are connected #
In this section we prove that a closed interval (hence, any OrdConnected
set) in a dense
conditionally complete linear order is preconnected.
A "continuous induction principle" for a closed interval: if a set s
meets [a, b]
on a closed subset, contains a
, and the set s ∩ [a, b)
has no maximal point, then b ∈ s
.
A "continuous induction principle" for a closed interval: if a set s
meets [a, b]
on a closed subset, contains a
, and for any a ≤ x < y ≤ b
, x ∈ s
, the set s ∩ (x, y]
is not empty, then [a, b] ⊆ s
.
A "continuous induction principle" for a closed interval: if a set s
meets [a, b]
on a closed subset, contains a
, and for any x ∈ s ∩ [a, b)
the set s
includes some open
neighborhood of x
within (x, +∞)
, then [a, b] ⊆ s
.
A closed interval in a densely ordered conditionally complete linear order is preconnected.
In a dense conditionally complete linear order, the set of preconnected sets is exactly
the set of the intervals Icc
, Ico
, Ioc
, Ioo
, Ici
, Ioi
, Iic
, Iio
, (-∞, +∞)
,
or ∅
. Though one can represent ∅
as (sInf s, sInf s)
, we include it into the list of
possible cases to improve readability.
This lemmas characterizes when a subset s
of a densely ordered conditionally complete linear
order is totally disconnected with respect to the order topology: between any two distinct points
of s
must lie a point not in s
.
Intermediate Value Theorem on an interval #
In this section we prove several versions of the Intermediate Value Theorem for a function continuous on an interval.
Intermediate Value Theorem for continuous functions on closed intervals, case
f a ≤ t ≤ f b
.
Intermediate Value Theorem for continuous functions on closed intervals, case
f a ≥ t ≥ f b
.
Intermediate Value Theorem for continuous functions on closed intervals, unordered case.
If f : α → α
is continuous on [[a, b]]
, a ≤ f a
, and f b ≤ b
,
then f
has a fixed point on [[a, b]]
.
If f : α → α
is continuous on [a, b]
, a ≤ b
, a ≤ f a
, and f b ≤ b
,
then f
has a fixed point on [a, b]
.
In particular, if [a, b]
is forward-invariant under f
,
then f
has a fixed point on [a, b]
, see exists_mem_Icc_isFixedPt_of_mapsTo
.
If a closed interval is forward-invariant under a continuous map f : α → α
,
then this map has a fixed point on this interval.
Intermediate value theorem: if f
is continuous on an order-connected set s
and a
,
b
are two points of this set, then f
sends s
to a superset of Icc (f x) (f y)
.
Intermediate value theorem: if f
is continuous on an order-connected set s
and a
,
b
are two points of this set, then f
sends s
to a superset of [f x, f y]
.
A continuous function which tendsto Filter.atTop
along Filter.atTop
and to atBot
along
at_bot
is surjective.
A continuous function which tendsto Filter.atBot
along Filter.atTop
and to Filter.atTop
along atBot
is surjective.
If a function f : α → β
is continuous on a nonempty interval s
, its restriction to s
tends to at_bot : Filter β
along at_bot : Filter ↥s
and tends to Filter.atTop : Filter β
along
Filter.atTop : Filter ↥s
, then the restriction of f
to s
is surjective. We formulate the
conclusion as Function.surjOn f s Set.univ
.
If a function f : α → β
is continuous on a nonempty interval s
, its restriction to s
tends to Filter.atTop : Filter β
along Filter.atBot : Filter ↥s
and tends to
Filter.atBot : Filter β
along Filter.atTop : Filter ↥s
, then the restriction of f
to s
is
surjective. We formulate the conclusion as Function.surjOn f s Set.univ
.
Suppose α
is equipped with a conditionally complete linear dense order and f : α → δ
is
continuous and injective. Then f
is strictly monotone (increasing) if
it is strictly monotone (increasing) on some closed interval [a, b]
.
Suppose f : [a, b] → δ
is
continuous and injective. Then f
is strictly monotone (increasing) if f(a) ≤ f(b)
.
Suppose f : [a, b] → δ
is
continuous and injective. Then f
is strictly antitone (decreasing) if f(b) ≤ f(a)
.
Suppose f : [a, b] → δ
is continuous and injective. Then f
is strictly monotone
or antitone (increasing or decreasing).
Suppose α
is equipped with a conditionally complete linear dense order and f : α → δ
is
continuous and injective. Then f
is strictly monotone or antitone (increasing or decreasing).
Every continuous injective f : (a, b) → δ
is strictly monotone
or antitone (increasing or decreasing).